Dictionary Definition
property
Noun
1 any area set aside for a particular purpose;
"who owns this place?"; "the president was concerned about the
property across from the White House" [syn: place]
2 something owned; any tangible or intangible
possession that is owned by someone; "that hat is my property"; "he
is a man of property"; [syn: belongings, holding, material
possession]
3 a basic or essential attribute shared by all
members of a class; "a study of the physical properties of atomic
particles"
4 a construct whereby objects or individuals can
be distinguished; "self-confidence is not an endearing property"
[syn: attribute,
dimension]
5 any movable articles or objects used on the set
of a play or movie; "before every scene he ran down his checklist
of props" [syn: prop]
User Contributed Dictionary
Noun
- Something that is owned.
- Leave those books alone! They are my property.
- A parcel of land with a single owner.
- There is a large house on the property.
- The exclusive right of possessing, enjoying, and disposing of a thing.
- Country property
- An attribute or abstract quality associated with an
object.
- Matter can have many properties, including color, mass and density.
- An editable parameter associated with an
application, or its
value.
- You need to set the debugging property to "verbose".
Derived terms
Related terms
Translations
something owned
- Arabic:
- Chinese: 財產, 财产 (cáichǎn)
- Croatian: vlasništvo
- Czech: majetek, vlastnictví
- Danish: ejendom , besiddelse
- Dutch: eigendom
- Faroese: ogn
- Finnish: omaisuus
- French: propriété
- German: Eigentum
- Greek: ιδιοκτησία (idioktisía)
- Hebrew:
- Hungarian: tulajdon
- Icelandic: eign
- Italian: proprietà
- Japanese: 財産, 資産, 所有物
- Korean: 재산 (jaesan)
- Norwegian: eiendom
- Portuguese: propriedade
- Russian: имущество (imúščestvo) , собственность (sóbstvennost’)
- Slovak: majetok
- Slovene: lastnina, last
- Spanish: propiedad
- Swedish: egendom
- Telugu: ఆస్తి (aasti)
piece of land with a single owner
- Croatian: imanje, gospodarstvo
- Czech: nemovitost
- Danish: ejendom
- Faroese: ogn
- Finnish: kiinteistö, tontti, määräala, tila
- German: Anwesen
- Greek: κτήμα (ktíma)
- Hebrew:
- Hungarian: ingatlan
- Icelandic: landeign , fasteign
- Japanese: 資産, 所有地
- Norwegian: eiendom
- Russian: собственность (sóbstvennost’)
- Spanish: propiedad, finca
- Telugu: ఆస్తి (aasti)
exclusive right of possessing, enjoying, and
disposing of a thing
- Danish: ejendomsret
- Faroese: ognarrættur
- Finnish: omistus, omistusoikeus
- German: Eigentum
- Greek: ιδιοκτησία (idioktisía)
- Hebrew:
- Japanese: 資産, 所有権
- Norwegian: eiendomsrett
- Russian: собственность (sóbstvennost’) , право собственности (právo sóbstvennosti)
- Slovene: lastništvo
country property
- Danish: ejendom , landejendom
- Faroese: ogn , landsogn
- Finnish: tila
- German: Eigenschaft
- Greek: κτήμα (ktíma)
- Norwegian: eiendom
- Russian: имущество (imúščestvo) , собственность (sóbstvennost’)
- Slovene: lastnina, last
- Telugu: గుణము (guNamu)
attribute or abstract quality associated with an
object
- Croatian: svojstvo
- Czech: vlastnost
- Danish: egenskab
- Faroese: eginleiki
- Finnish: ominaisuus
- German: Eigenschaft
- Greek: ιδιότητα (idiótita)
- Hebrew: ,
- Hungarian: tulajdonság
- Japanese: 特徴, 特性
- Norwegian: egenskap
- Russian: свойство, качество
- Slovene: lastnost
- Spanish: propriedad (obsolete), propiedad
- Swedish: egenskap
- West Frisian: eigenskip
computing: an editable parameter associated with
an application, or its value
- ttbc Afrikaans: besitting
- ttbc Albanian: pronë
- ttbc Arabic: (milkíyya)
- ttbc Azerbaijani: mülkiyyət
- ttbc Bosnian: vlasništvo
- ttbc Bulgarian: имот (imot)
- ttbc Catalan: hisenda
- ttbc Chinese: 财产 (cáichǎn)
- ttbc Dutch: eigendom, eigenschap
- ttbc Esperanto: propraĵo
- ttbc Estonian: vara
- ttbc French: propriété
- ttbc Georgian: საკუთრება (sak’ut’reba)
- ttbc Hindi: gunasvabhava, adhikara, jayadada, samagri, sanpatti
- ttbc Hungarian: birtok
- ttbc Indonesian: milik
- ttbc Irish: sealúchas
- ttbc Italian: proprietà
- ttbc Korean: 재산 (jaesan)
- ttbc Latin: vicus
- ttbc Latvian: īpašība
- ttbc Lithuanian: turtas
- ttbc Mongolian: хeрeнгe хогшил (herenge hogšil)
- ttbc Norwegian: eiendom
- ttbc Old English: æht
- ttbc Papiamento: kalidat
- ttbc Persian: (dārāyi)
- ttbc Polish: własność
- ttbc Portuguese: propriedade
- ttbc Romanian: proprietate
- ttbc Serbian: власништво (vlasništvo)
- ttbc Swahili: hozi
- ttbc Swedish: egendom
- ttbc Tagalog: pag-aari
- ttbc Thai: (sìttíkrôpkrong)
- ttbc Turkish: mülkiyet
- ttbc Ukrainian: власність (vlásnist’)
- ttbc Uyghur: ewqat
- ttbc Vietnamese: quyền sở hữu
- ttbc Welsh: eiddo
- ttbc Yiddish: farmog
- ttbc Zulu: ilipulazi
Extensive Definition
Property means Right of Action for things that
can be exchanged. Important types of property include real property (land), personal
property (other physical possessions), and intellectual
property (rights over artistic creations, inventions, etc.). A
right of ownership is associated with
property that establishes the good as being "one's own thing" in
relation to other individuals or groups, assuring the owner the
right to dispense with the property in a manner he or she sees fit,
whether to use or not use, exclude others from using, or to
transfer ownership. Some philosophers assert that property rights
arise from social
convention. Others find origins for them in morality or natural law
(e.g. Saint
Irenaeus).
Use of the term
Various scholarly communities (e.g., law, economics, anthropology, sociology) may treat the concept more systematically, but definitions vary within and between fields. Scholars in the social sciences frequently conceive of property as a bundle of rights. They stress that property is not a relationship between people and things, but a relationship between people with regard to things.Public
property is any property that is controlled by a state or by a
whole community. Private
property is any property that is not public property. Private
property may be under the control of a single individual or by a
group of individuals collectively. Some philosophers like Karl Marx use
it to describe a social relationship between those who sell their
labor power and those who buy it.
General characteristics
Modern property rights conceive of ownership and possession as belonging to legal individuals, even if the legal individual is not a real person. Corporations, for example, have legal rights similar to American citizens, including many of their constitutional rights. Therefore, the corporation is a juristic person or artificial legal entity, which some refer to as "corporate personhood".Property rights are protected in the current laws
of states usually found in the form of a Constitution
or a Bill of
Rights. The fifth and the fourteenth amendments to the United
States constitution, for example, provide explicitly for the
protection of private property:
The
Fifth Amendment states:
- Nor be deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor shall private property be taken for public use, without just compensation.
The
Fourteenth Amendment states:
- No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.
Protection is also found in the United Nations's
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Article 17, and in the
French
Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, Article
XVII, and in the
European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR), Protocol 1.
Property is usually thought of in terms of a
bundle of
rights as defined and protected by the local sovereignty. Ownership,
however, does not necessarily equate with sovereignty. If ownership
gave supreme authority it would be sovereignty, not ownership.
These are two different concepts.
Traditional principles of property rights
includes:
Traditional property rights do not include:
- uses that unreasonably interfere with the property rights of another private party (the right of quiet enjoyment). [See Nuisance]
- uses that unreasonably interfere with public property rights, including uses that interfere with public health, safety, peace or convenience. [See Public Nuisance, Police Power]
Legal systems have evolved to cover the
transactions and disputes which arise over the possession, use,
transfer and disposal of property, most particularly involving
contracts. Positive law
defines such rights, and a judiciary is used to
adjudicate and to enforce.
In his classic text, "The Common Law",
Oliver Wendell Holmes describes property as having two
fundamental aspects. The first is possession, which can be defined
as control over a resource based on the practical inability of
another to contradict the ends of the possessor. The second is
title, which is the expectation that others will recognize rights
to control resource, even when it is not in possession. He
elaborates the differences between these two concepts, and proposes
a history of how they came to be attached to individuals, as
opposed to families or entities such as the church.
According to Adam Smith,
the expectation of profit from "improving one's stock of capital"
rests on private property rights, and the belief that property
rights encourage the property holders to develop the property,
generate wealth, and
efficiently allocate resources
based on the operation of the market is central to capitalism. From this evolved
the modern conception of property as a right which is enforced by
positive law, in the expectation that this would produce more
wealth and better standards of living.
- Classical liberals, Objectivists, and related traditions
-
- "Just as man can't exist without his body, so no rights can exist without the right to translate one's rights into reality, to think, to work and keep the results, which means: the right of property." (Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged)
- Most thinkers from these traditions subscribe to the labor theory of property. They hold that you own your own life, and it follows that you must own the products of that life, and that those products can be traded in free exchange with others.
-
- "Every man has a property in his own person. This nobody has a right to, but himself." (John Locke, Second Treatise on Civil Government)
-
- "Life, liberty, and property do not exist because men have made laws. On the contrary, it was the fact that life, liberty, and property existed beforehand that caused men to make laws in the first place." (Frédéric Bastiat, The Law)
-
- "The reason why men enter into society is the preservation of their property." (John Locke, Second Treatise on Civil Government)
- Socialism's fundamental principles are centered on a critique of this concept, stating, among other things, that the cost of defending property is higher than the returns from private property ownership, and that even when property rights encourage the property-holder to develop his property, generate wealth, etc., he will only do so for his own benefit, which may not coincide with the benefit of other people or society at large
- Libertarian socialism generally accepts property rights, but with a short abandonment time period. In other words, a person must make (more or less) continuous use of the item or else he loses ownership rights. This is usually referred to as "possession property" or "usufruct." Thus, in this usufruct system, absentee ownership is illegitimate, and workers own the machines they work with.
- Communism argues that only collective ownership of the means of production through a polity (though not necessarily a state) will assure the minimization of unequal or unjust outcomes and the maximization of benefits, and that therefore private property (which in communist theory is limited to capital) should be abolished.Both communism and some kinds of socialism have also upheld the notion that private property is inherently illegitimate. This argument is centered mainly on the idea that the creation of private property will always benefit one class over another, giving way to domination through the use of this private property. Communists are naturally not opposed to personal property which is "Hard-won, self-acquired, self-earned" (Communist Manifesto), by members of the proletariat.
Not every person, or entity, with an interest in a
given piece of property may be able to exercise all of the rights
mentioned a few paragraphs above. For example, as a lessee of a particular piece of
property, you may not sell the property, because the tenant is only
in possession, and does not have title to transfer. Similarly,
while you are a lessee the owner cannot use his or her
right to exclude to keep
you from the property. (Or, if he or she does you may perhaps be
entitled to stop paying rent or perhaps sue to regain
access.)
Further, property may be held in a number of
forms, e.g. joint
ownership, community
property, sole
ownership, lease, etc.
These different types of ownership may complicate an owner's
ability to exercise his
or her rights unilaterally. For example if two people own a single
piece of land as joint tenants, then depending on the law in the
jurisdiction, each
may have limited recourse for the actions of the other. For
example, one of the owners might sell his or her interest in the property to a
stranger that the other owner does not particularly like.
Theories of property
There exist many theories. Perhaps one of the most popular was the natural rights definition of property rights as advanced by John Locke. Locke advanced the theory that when one mixes one’s labor with nature, one gains ownership of that part of nature with which the labor is mixed, subject to the limitation that there should be "enough, and as good, left in common for others"http://www.constitution.org/jl/2ndtr05.txt.From the RERUM NOVARUM, Pope Leo
XIII wrote "It is surely undeniable that, when a man engages in
remunerative labor, the impelling reason and motive of his work is
to obtain property, and thereafter to hold it as his very
own."
Anthropology studies the diverse systems of
ownership, rights of use and transfer, and possession under the
term "theories of property". Western legal theory is based, as
mentioned, on the owner of property being a legal individual.
However, not all property systems are founded on this basis.
In every culture studied ownership and possession
are the subject of custom and regulation, and "law" where the term
can meaningfully be applied. Many tribal cultures balance
individual ownership with the laws of collective groups: tribes,
families, associations and nations. For example the 1839 Cherokee
Constitution frames the issue in these terms:
- Sec. 2. The lands of the Cherokee Nation shall remain common property; but the improvements made thereon, and in the possession of the citizens respectively who made, or may rightfully be in possession of them: Provided, that the citizens of the Nation possessing exclusive and indefeasible right to their improvements, as expressed in this article, shall possess no right or power to dispose of their improvements, in any manner whatever, to the United States, individual States, or to individual citizens thereof; and that, whenever any citizen shall remove with his effects out of the limits of this Nation, and become a citizen of any other government, all his rights and privileges as a citizen of this Nation shall cease: Provided, nevertheless, That the National Council shall have power to re-admit, by law, to all the rights of citizenship, any such person or persons who may, at any time, desire to return to the Nation, on memorializing the National Council for such readmission.
Communal property systems describe ownership as
belonging to the entire social and political unit, while corporate
systems describe ownership as being attached to an identifiable
group with an identifiable responsible individual. The Roman
property law was based on such a corporate system.
Different societies may have different theories
of property for differing types of ownership. Pauline
Peters argued that property systems are not isolable from the
social fabric, and notions of property may not be stated as such,
but instead may be framed in negative terms: for example the taboo
system among Polynesian peoples.
http://propertyimpian.blogspot.com/2007/06/theories-of-property-natural-rights.html
Property in philosophy
In medieval and Renaissance Europe the term "property" essentially referred to land. Much rethinking was necessary in order for land to come to be regarded as only a special case of the property genus. This rethinking was inspired by at least three broad features of early modern Europe: the surge of commerce, the breakdown of efforts to prohibit interest (then called "usury"), and the development of centralized national monarchies.Ancient philosophy
Urukagina, the king of the Sumerian city-state Lagash, established the first laws that forbade compelling the sale of property. The Cyrus cylinder of Cyrus the Great, founder of the Achaemenid Persian Empire, documents the protection of property rights.The Ten
Commandments shown in Exodus 20:2-17 and Deuteronomy 5:6-21
stated that the Israelites were
not to steal. These texts, written in approximately 1300 B.C., were
a blanket early protection of private property.
Aristotle, in
Politics, advocates "private property." In one of the first known
expositions of tragedy
of the commons he says, "that which is common to the greatest
number has the least care bestowed upon it. Every one thinks
chiefly of his own, hardly at all of the common interest; and only
when he is himself concerned as an individual." In addition, he
says when property is common there are natural problems that arise
due to differences in labor: "If they do not share equally
enjoyments and toils, those who labor much and get little will
necessarily complain of those who labor little and receive or
consume much. But indeed there is always a difficulty in men living
together and having all human relations in common, but especially
in their having common property." (Politics,
1261b34)
Pre-industrial English philosophy
Thomas Hobbes (1600s)
The principal writings of Thomas
Hobbes appeared between 1640 and 1651—during
and immediately following the
war between forces loyal to King Charles
I and those loyal to Parliament. In
his own words, Hobbes' reflection began with the idea of "giving to
every man his own," a phrase he drew from the writings of Cicero. But he
wondered: How can anybody call anything his own? In that unsettled
time and place it perhaps was natural that he would conclude: My
own can only truly be mine if there is one unambiguously strongest
power in the realm, and that power treats it as mine, protecting
its status as such.
James Harrington (1600s)
A contemporary of Hobbes, James
Harrington, reacted differently to the same tumult; he
considered property natural but not inevitable. The author of
Oceana, he
may have been the first political theorist to postulate that
political power is a consequence, not the cause, of the
distribution of property. He said that the worst possible situation
is one in which the commoners have half a nation's property, with
crown and nobility holding the other half—a circumstance
fraught with instability and violence. A much better situation (a
stable republic) will exist once the commoners own most property,
he suggested.
In later years, the ranks of Harrington's
admirers would include American revolutionary and founder John
Adams.
Robert Filmer (1600s)
Another member of the Hobbes/Harrington
generation, Sir Robert
Filmer, reached conclusions much like Hobbes', but through
Biblical
exegesis. Filmer said
that the institution of kingship is analogous to that of
fatherhood, that subjects are but children, whether obedient or
unruly, and that property rights are akin to the household goods
that a father may dole out among his children—his to take
back and dispose of according to his pleasure.
John Locke (1600s)
In the following generation, John Locke
sought to answer Filmer, creating a rationale for a balanced
constitution in
which the monarch would have a part to play, but not an
overwhelming part. Since Filmer's views essentially require that
the Stuart
family be uniquely descended from the patriarchs of the Bible, and since even
in the late seventeenth
century that was a difficult view to uphold, Locke attacked
Filmer's views in his
First Treatise on Civil Government, freeing him to set out his
own views in the
Second Treatise on Civil Government. Therein, Locke imagined a
pre-social world, the unhappy residents of which create a social
contract. They would, he allowed, create a monarchy, but its task would be
to execute the will of an elected legislature.
"To this end" he wrote, meaning the end of their
own long life and peace, "it is that men give up all their natural
power to the society they enter into, and the community put the
legislative
power into such hands as they think fit, with this trust, that
they shall be governed by declared laws, or else their peace,
quiet, and property will still be at the same uncertainty as it was
in the state of
nature."
Even when it keeps to proper legislative form,
though, Locke held that there are limits to what a government
established by such a contract might rightly do.
"It cannot be supposed that [the hypothetical
contractors] they should intend, had they a power so to do, to give
any one or more an absolute arbitrary power over their persons and
estates, and put a force into the magistrate's hand to execute his
unlimited will arbitrarily upon them; this were to put themselves
into a worse condition than the state of nature, wherein they had a
liberty to defend their right against the injuries of others, and
were upon equal terms of force to maintain it, whether invaded by a
single man or many in combination. Whereas by supposing they have
given up themselves to the absolute arbitrary power and will of a
legislator, they have disarmed themselves, and armed him to make a
prey of them when he pleases..."
Note that both "persons and estates" are to be
protected from the arbitrary power of any magistrate, inclusive of
the "power and will of a legislator." In Lockean terms,
depredations against an estate are just as plausible a
justification for resistance and revolution as are those against
persons. In neither case are subjects required to allow themselves
to become prey.
To explain the ownership of property Locke
advanced a labor
theory of property.
William Blackstone (1700s)
In the 1760s, William
Blackstone sought to codify the English common law. In
his famous
Commentaries on the Laws of England he wrote that "every wanton
and causeless restraint of the will of the subject, whether
produced by a monarch, a nobility, or a popular assembly is a
degree of tyranny."
How should such tyranny be prevented or resisted?
Through property rights, Blackstone thought, which is why he
emphasized that indemnification must be awarded a non-consenting
owner whose property is taken by eminent
domain, and that a property owner is protected against physical
invasion of his property by the laws of trespass and nuisance. Indeed, he wrote that
a landowner is free to kill any stranger on his property between
dusk and dawn, even an agent of the King, since it isn't reasonable
to expect him to recognize the King's agents in the dark.
David Hume (1700s)
In contrast to the figures discussed in this
section thus far, David Hume
lived a relatively quiet life that had settled down to a relatively
stable social and political structure. He lived the life of a
solitary writer until 1763 when, at 52 years of age, he went off to
Paris to work
at the British embassy.
In contrast, one might think, to his
outrage-generating works on religion and his skeptical
views in epistemology, Hume's views
on law and property were quite conservative.
He did not believe in hypothetical contracts, or
in the love of mankind in general, and sought to ground politics
upon actual human beings as one knows them. "In general," he wrote,
"it may be affirmed that there is no such passion in human mind, as
the love of mankind, merely as such, independent of personal
qualities, or services, or of relation to ourselves." Existing
customs should not lightly be disregarded, because they have come
to be what they are as a result of human nature. With this
endorsement of custom comes an endorsement of existing governments,
because he conceived of the two as complementary: "A regard for
liberty, though a
laudable passion, ought commonly to be subordinate to a reverence
for established government."
These views led to a view on property rights that
might today be described as legal
positivism. There are property rights because of and to the
extent that the existing law, supported by social customs, secure
them. He offered some practical home-spun advice on the general
subject, though, as when he referred to avarice as "the spur of industry," and expressed
concern about excessive levels of taxation, which "destroy
industry, by engendering despair."
Critique and response
By the mid 19th century, the industrial revolution had transformed England and had begun in France. The established conception of what constitutes property expanded beyond land to encompass scarce goods in general. In France, the revolution of the 1790s had led to large-scale confiscation of land formerly owned by church and king. The restoration of the monarchy led to claims by those dispossessed to have their former lands returned. Furthermore, the labor theory of value popularized by classical economists such as Adam Smith and David Ricardo were utilized by a new ideology called socialism to critique the relations of property to other economic issues, such as profit, rent, interest, and wage-labor. Thus, property was no longer an esoteric philosophical question, but a political issue of substantial concern.Charles Comte - legitimate origin of property
Charles
Comte, in Traité de la propriété (1834), attempted to justify
the legitimacy of private property in response to the Bourbon
Restoration. According to David Hart, Comte had three main
points: "firstly, that interference by the state over the centuries
in property ownership has had dire consequences for justice as well
as for economic productivity; secondly, that property is legitimate
when it emerges in such a way as not to harm anyone; and thirdly,
that historically some, but by no means all, property which has
evolved has done so legitimately, with the implication that the
present distribution of property is a complex mixture of
legitimately and illegitimately held titles." (The
Radical Liberalism of Charles Comte and Charles Dunoyer
Comte, as Proudhon would later do, rejected
Roman legal
tradition with its toleration of slavery. He posited a communal
"national" property consisting of non-scarce goods, such as land in
ancient hunter-gatherer societies. Since agriculture was so much
more efficient than hunting and gathering, private property
appropriated by someone for farming left remaining hunter-gatherers
with more land per person, and hence did not harm them. Thus this
type of land appropriation did not violate the Lockean
proviso - there was "still enough, and as good left." Comte's
analysis would be used by later theorists in response to the
socialist critique on property.
Pierre Proudhon - property is theft
In his 1849 treatise What is
Property?, Pierre
Proudhon answers with "Property
is theft!" In natural resources, he sees two types of property,
de jure property (legal title) and de facto property (physical
possession), and argues that the former is illegitimate. Proudhon's
conclusion is that "property, to be just and possible, must
necessarily have equality for its condition."
His analysis of the product of labor upon natural
resources as property (usufruct) is more nuanced. He asserts that
land itself cannot be property, yet it should be held by individual
possessors as stewards of mankind with the product of labor being
the property of the producer. Proudhon reasoned that any wealth
gained without labor was stolen from those who labored to create
that wealth. Even a voluntary contract to surrender the product of
labor to an employer was theft, according to Proudhon, since the
controller of natural resources had no moral right to charge others
for the use of that which he did not labor to create and therefore
did not own.
Proudhon's theory of property greatly influenced
the budding socialist movement, inspiring anarchist theorists such
as Mikhail
Bakunin who modified Proudhon's ideas, as well as antagonizing
theorists like Karl
Marx.
Frédéric Bastiat - property is value
Frédéric
Bastiat's main treatise on property can be found in chapter 8
of his book Economic Harmonies (1850).http://www.econlib.org/library/Bastiat/basHar.html
In a radical departure from traditional property theory, he defines
property not as a physical object, but rather as a relationship
between people with respect to an object. Thus, saying one owns a
glass of water is merely verbal shorthand for I may justly gift or
trade this water to another person. In essence, what one owns is
not the object but the value of the object. By "value," Bastiat
apparently means market value; he emphasizes that this is quite
different from utility. "In our relations with one another, we are
not owners of the utility of things, but of their value, and value
is the appraisal made of reciprocal services."
Strongly disputing Proudhon's equality-based
argument, Bastiat theorizes that, as a result of technological
progress and the division of labor, the stock of communal wealth
increases over time; that the hours of work an unskilled laborer
expends to buy e.g. 100 liters of wheat decreases over time, thus
amounting to "gratis" satisfaction. Thus, private property
continually destroys itself, becoming transformed into communal
wealth. The increasing proportion of communal wealth to private
property results in a tendency toward equality of mankind. ''"Since
the human race started from the point of greatest poverty, that is,
from the point where there were the most obstacles to be overcome,
it is clear that all that has been gained from one era to the next
has been due to the spirit of property."''
This transformation of private property into the
communal domain, Bastiat points out, does not imply that private
property will ever totally disappear. This is because man, as he
progresses, continually invents new and more sophisticated needs
and desires.
Contemporary views
Among contemporary political thinkers who believe that human individuals enjoy rights to own property and to enter into contracts, there are two views about John Locke. On the one hand there are ardent Locke admirers, such as W.H. Hutt (1956), who praised Locke for laying down the "quintessence of individualism." On the other hand, there are those such as Richard Pipes who think that Locke's arguments are weak, and that undue reliance thereon has weakened the cause of individualism in recent times. Pipes has written that Locke's work "marked a regression because it rested on the concept of Natural Law" rather than upon Harrington's sociological framework.
Hernando de Soto has argued that an important characteristic of
capitalist market economy is the functioning state protection of
property rights in a formal property system where ownership and
transactions are clearly recorded. These property rights and the
whole formal system of property make possible:
- Greater independence for individuals from local community arrangements to protect their assets;
- Clear, provable, and protectable ownership;
- The standardization and integration of property rules and property information in the country as a whole;
- Increased trust arising from a greater certainty of punishment for cheating in economic transactions;
- More formal and complex written statements of ownership that permit the easier assumption of shared risk and ownership in companies, and insurance against risk;
- Greater availability of loans for new projects, since more things could be used as collateral for the loans;
- Easier access to and more reliable information regarding such things as credit history and the worth of assets;
- Increased fungibility, standardization and transferability of statements documenting the ownership of property, which paves the way for structures such as national markets for companies and the easy transportation of property through complex networks of individuals and other entities;
- Greater protection of biodiversity due to minimizing of shifting agriculture practices.
Types of property
Most legal
systems distinguish different types (immovable
property, estate in
land, real estate,
real
property) of property, especially between land and all other
forms of property - goods
and chattels, movable
property or personal
property. They often distinguish tangible and intangible
property (see below).
One categorization scheme specifies three species
of property: land, improvements (immovable man made things) and
personal property (movable man made things)
In common law,
real
property (immovable
property) is the combination of interests in land and
improvements thereto and personal
property is interest in movable property.
'Real property' rights are rights relating to the
land. These rights include ownership and usage. Owners can grant
rights to persons and entities in the form of leases, licenses and
easements.
Later, with the development of more complex forms
of non-tangible property, personal property was divided into
tangible property (such as cars, clothing, animals) and intangible or
abstract
property (e.g. financial
instruments such as stocks and bonds,
etc.), which includes intellectual
property (patents,
copyrights, and
trademarks).
What can be property?
The two major justifications given for original property, or homesteading, are effort and scarcity. John Locke emphasized effort, "mixing your labor" with an object, or clearing and cultivating virgin land. Benjamin Tucker preferred to look at the telos of property, i.e. What is the purpose of property? His answer: to solve the scarcity problem. Only when items are relatively scarce with respect to people's desires do they become property.http://www.zetetics.com/mac/libdebates/ch6intpr.html For example, hunter-gatherers did not consider land to be property, since there was no shortage of land. Agrarian societies later made arable land property, as it was scarce. For something to be economically scarce, it must necessarily have the exclusivity property - that use by one person excludes others from using it. These two justifications lead to different conclusions on what can be property. Intellectual property - non-corporeal things like ideas, plans, orderings and arrangements (musical compositions, novels, computer programs) - are generally considered valid property to those who support an effort justification, but invalid to those who support a scarcity justification (since they don't have the exclusivity property.) Thus even ardent propertarians may disagree about IP.http://praxeology.net/anticopyright.htm By either standard, one's body is one's property.From some anarchist points of view, the
validity of property depends on whether the "property right"
requires enforcement by the state. Different forms of "property"
require different amounts of enforcement: intellectual
property requires a great deal of state intervention to
enforce, ownership of distant physical property requires quite a
lot, ownership of carried objects requires very little, while
ownership of one's own body requires absolutely no state
intervention.
Many things have existed that did not have an
owner, sometimes called
the commons. The term
"commons," however, is also often used to mean something quite
different: "general collective ownership" - i.e. common ownership.
Also, the same term is sometimes used by statists to mean
government-owned property that the general public is allowed to
access. Law in all societies has tended to develop towards reducing
the number of things not having clear owners. Supporters of
property rights argue that this enables better protection of scarce
resources, due to the tragedy
of the commons, while critics argue that it leads to the
exploitation of those resources for personal gain and that it
hinders taking advantage of potential network
effects. These arguments have differing validity for different
types of "property" -- things which are not scarce are, for
instance, not subject to the tragedy
of the commons. Some apparent critics actually are advocating
general collective ownership rather than ownerlessness.
Things today which do not have owners include:
ideas (except for intellectual
property), seawater
(which is, however, protected by anti-pollution laws), parts of the
seafloor (see the
United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea for
restrictions), gasses in Earth's
atmosphere, animals in the wild (though there may be
restrictions on hunting etc. -- and in some legal systems, such as
that of New York, they are actually treated as government
property), celestial bodies and outer space, and land in Antarctica.
The nature of children under the age of
majority is another contested issue here. In ancient societies
children were generally considered the property of their parents.
Children in most modern societies theoretically own their own
bodies -- but they are considered incompetent to exercise their
rights, and their parents or guardians
are given most of the actual rights of control over them.
Questions regarding the nature of ownership of
the body also come up in the issue of abortion and drugs.
In many ancient legal systems (e.g. early
Roman
law), religious sites (e.g. temples) were considered property
of the God or
gods they were devoted to. However, religious pluralism
makes it more convenient to have religious sites owned by the
religious
body that runs them.
Intellectual
property and air (airspace, no-fly zone,
pollution laws, which can include tradeable emissions
rights) can be property in some senses of the word.
Rights of use as property
Ownership of land can be held separately from the ownership of rights over that land, including sporting rightshttp://www.basc.org.uk/media/2001_definition_of_sporting_rights.pdf, mineral rights, development rights, air rights, and such other rights as may be worth segregating from simple land ownership.Who can be an owner?
Ownership laws may vary widely among countries depending on the nature of the property of interest (e.g. firearms, real property, personal property, animals). In some societies only adult men may own property. In many societies legal entities, such as corporations, trusts, and nations (or governments) own property.In the Inca empire, the dead emperors, who were
considered gods, still controlled property after death..
References
See also
Property taking (legal)
- Confiscation
- Eminent domain
- Fine
- Regulatory fees and costs
- Search and seizure
- Tariffs
- Tax
- Turf and twig (historical)
- Tithe, Zakat (historical sense)
- Zoning restrictions
- RS 2477
Property taking (illegal)
Property of either digital or virtual form
Property economists
References
- Frédéric Bastiat, 1850. Economic Harmonies. W. Hayden Boyers, trans.; George B. de Huszar, ed. Liberty Fund.
- --------, 1850. The Law. Dean Russell, trans.
- Tom Bethell, 1998. The Noblest Triumph: Property and Prosperity through the Ages. New York: St. Martin's Press.
- William Blackstone, 1765-69. Commentaries on the Laws of England, 4 vols. Oxford Univ. Press. Especially Books the Second and Third.
- Hernando De Soto, 1989. The Other Path. Harper & Row.
- Hernando De Soto and Francis Cheneval, 2006. Realizing Property Rights. Ruffer & Rub.
- Ellickson, Robert, 1993, "", Yale Law Journal 102: 1315-1400.
- Richard Pipes, 1999. Property and Freedom.
- Mckay, John P. , 2004, "A History of World Societes". Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company
External links and references
- Property Law Case Summaries
- Private Property, Freedom, and the Rule of Law
- "Right to Private Property", Tibor Machan, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- "The Ethics and Economics of Private Property", Hans-Hermann Hoppe, van Mises Institute
property in Czech: Vlastnictví
property in German: Eigentum
property in Esperanto: Posedo
property in Estonian: Omand
property in Spanish: Propiedad
property in French: Droit de propriété
property in Korean: 재산권
property in Ido: Proprietajo
property in Indonesian: Properti
property in Icelandic: Eignarréttur
property in Italian: Proprietà (diritto)
property in Hebrew: רכוש
property in Georgian: საკუთრება
property in Dutch: Eigendom
property in Japanese: 財産権
property in Norwegian: Eiendom
property in Polish: Mienie
property in Portuguese: Propriedade
privada
property in Russian: Собственность
property in Simple English: Property
property in Swedish: Fastighet
property in Tamil: சொத்துரிமை
property in Turkish: Mülkiyet
property in Urdu: جائیداد
property in Yiddish: אייגענטום
property in Chinese: 財產權
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
acreage, acres, adverse possession,
affection, affluence, alodium, aroma, assets, attribute, available means,
badge, balance, banner, belongings, blackface, body-build,
bottomless purse, brand,
bulging purse, burgage,
cachet, capital, capital goods, capitalization, cast, character, characteristic, characteristics,
chattels, chattels
real, claim, clown white,
colony, complexion, composition, configuration, constituents, constitution, costume, crasis, cut, de facto, de jure, demesne, dependency, derivative title,
device, dharma, diathesis, differentia, differential, disposition, distinctive
feature, domain, dominion, earmark, easy circumstances,
effects, embarras de
richesses, estate,
ethos, feature, fee fief, fee position,
fee simple, fee simple absolute, fee simple conditional, fee simple
defeasible, fee simple determinable, fee tail, feodum, feud, fiber, fiefdom, figure, flavor, fortune, frame, frankalmoign, free socage,
freehold, fund, gavelkind, gear, genius, gold, grain, greasepaint, grist, grounds, gust, habit, hallmark, handsome fortune,
having title to, high income, high tax bracket, hold, holding, holdings, honor, hue, humor, humors, idiocrasy, idiosyncrasy, ilk, image, impress, impression, independence, index, indicant, indicator, individualism, insignia, keynote, kind, knight service, land, landed property, lands, lay fee, lease, leasehold, legal claim, legal
possession, lineaments, liquid assets,
lot, lots, lucre, luxuriousness, makeup, mammon, mandate, mannerism, manor, mark, marking, material wealth,
means, measure, messuage, mold, money, money to burn, moneybags, nature, note, occupancy, occupation, oddity, odor, opulence, opulency, original title,
owning, paraphernalia, parcel, particularity, peculiarity, pelf, physique, picture, plat, plot, possessing, possession, possessions, possessorship, practical
piece, praedium,
preoccupancy,
preoccupation,
prepossession,
prescription,
prop, property rights,
proprietary,
proprietary rights, proprietorship, prosperity, prosperousness, quadrat, quality, quiddity, quirk, real estate, real property,
realty, representation, representative, resource, resources, riches, richness, savor, seal, seisin, shape, sigil, sign, signal, signature, singularity, six-figure
income, smack, socage, somatotype, sort, specialty, spirit, squatting, stamp, streak, stripe, sublease, substance, suchness, supply, sure sign, symptom, system, taint, tang, taste, telltale sign, temper, temperament, tenancy, tenantry, tendency, tenements, tenor, tenure, tenure in chivalry,
theatrical makeup, title,
toft, token, tone, trait, treasure, trick, type, underlease, undertenancy, upper
bracket, usucapion,
vein, villein socage,
villeinhold,
villenage, virtue, way, wealth, wealthiness, worth