Dictionary Definition
philosophy
Noun
1 a belief (or system of beliefs) accepted as
authoritative by some group or school [syn: doctrine, philosophical
system, school of
thought, ism]
2 the rational investigation of questions about
existence and knowledge and ethics
3 any personal belief about how to live or how to
deal with a situation; "self-indulgence was his only philosophy";
"my father's philosophy of child-rearing was to let mother do
it"
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Etymology
From sc=polytonic from sc=polytonic & sc=polytonic.Pronunciation
- /fɪlˈɒsəfi/
Noun
- An academic discipline that is often divided into five major branches: logic; metaphysics; epistemology; ethics; and aesthetics.
- A comprehensive system of belief.
- A view or outlook regarding fundamental principles underlying some
domain.
- a philosophy of government
- a philosophy of education
- a philosophy of government
- A general principle (usually moral).
Translations
academic discipline
- Arabic: (fálsafa)
- Chinese: 哲学 (zhéxué)
- Croatian: filozofija
- Czech: filozofie, filosofie
- Dutch: filosofie
- Esperanto: filozofio
- Finnish: filosofia
- French: philosophie
- German: Philosophie
- Hungarian: filozófia
- Italian: filosofia
- Japanese: 哲学 (てつがく, tetsugaku)
- Korean: 철학 (cheolhak)
- Latin: philosophia
- Portuguese: filosofia
- Russian: философия
- Spanish: filosofía
- Swedish: filosofi
comprehensive system of belief
- Arabic: (fálsafa) ,
- Croatian: filozofija
- Czech: filozofie
- Esperanto: filozofio
- Finnish: filosofia
- Hungarian: filozófia
- Russian: философия
- Swedish: filosofi
view regarding fundamental principles
- Arabic: ,
- Croatian: filozofija
- Finnish: filosofia
- Hungarian: filozófia
- Russian: философия
- Swedish: filosofi
general principle
- Arabic: ,
- Croatian: filozofija
- Finnish: filosofia, periaate
- Hungarian: filozófia
- Swedish: filosofi
- ttbc Italian: filosofia
- ttbc Bosnian: filozofija
- ttbc Catalan: filosofia
- ttbc Chinese: 哲学 (zhéxué)
- ttbc Dutch: filosofie , wijsbegeerte
- ttbc Estonian: filosoofia
- ttbc French: philosophie
- ttbc German: Philosophie
- ttbc Greek: φιλοσοφία (filosofía) (1,2,3,4), κοσμοθεωρία (kozmotheoria) (2)
- ttbc Icelandic: heimspeki
- ttbc Japanese: 哲学 (てつがく, tetsugaku)
- ttbc Lithuanian: filosofija
- ttbc Maltese: filosofija
- ttbc Polish: filozofia
- ttbc Portuguese: filosofia
- ttbc Romanian: filosofie/filozofie
- ttbc Serbian:
- Cyrillic:
филозофија
- Roman: filozofija
- Cyrillic:
филозофија
- ttbc Spanish: filosofía
- ttbc Telugu: తత్వం (tatvaM), తాత్వికత h(taatvikata)
- ttbc Ukrainian: філософія (filosofija)
Extensive Definition
Philosophy is "the study of the most general and
abstract features of the world and categories with which we think:
mind, matter, reason, proof, truth etc. In philosophy, the concepts
by which we approach the world themselves become the topic of
enquiry." The main branches of philosophy are logic, epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, as well as philosophy
of mind, political
philosophy, and aesthetics. . Its
investigations use reason, striving to make no unexamined
assumptions.
The word philosophy is of Ancient
Greek origin:
φιλοσοφία (philosophía), meaning "love of knowledge", "love of
wisdom".
The philosophers of East and
South
Asia are discussed in Eastern
philosophy, while the philosophers of North Africa
and the Middle East,
because of their strong interactions with Europe, are usually
considered part of Western
philosophy.
Branches of philosophy
To give an exhaustive list of the main branches
of philosophy is difficult, because there have been different,
equally acceptable divisions at different times, and the divisions
are often relative to the concerns of a particular period. However,
the following branches are usually accepted as the main ones.
Metaphysics
investigates the nature of being and the world. Traditional
branches are cosmology
and ontology.
Epistemology
is concerned with the nature and scope of knowledge, and whether
knowledge is possible. Among its central concerns has been the
challenge posed by skepticism and the
relationships between truth, belief and justification.
Ethics, or 'moral
philosophy', is concerned with questions of how persons ought to
act or if such questions are answerable. Plato's early
dialogues include a search for definitions of virtue. Metaethics
compares and contrasts various systems of ethics, and investigates
what ethics is. Ethics is also associated with ideas of morality.
Philosophy
of Mind deals with the nature of the mind an its relationship
to the body, and is typified by disputes between dualism and materialism. In recent years
there is an increasing connection between this branch of philosophy
and cognitive
science
Logic deals with
patters of thinking that lead from true premises to true
conclusions. Beginning in the late 19th
century, mathematicians such as
Frege began a
mathematical treatment of logic, and today the subject of logic has
two broad divisions: mathematical
logic (formal symbolic logic) and what is now called philosophical
logic.
Aesthetics deals
with beauty, art, enjoyment, sensory-emotional values, perception,
and matters of taste and sentiment.
Political
Philosophy is the study of government and the relationship of
individuals and communities to the state. In includes questions
about law, property, and the rights and obligations of the
citizen.
Most academic subjects have a philosophy, for
example the philosophy
of science, the philosophy
of mathematics, and the philosophy
of history. In addition a range of academic subjects have
emerged to deal with areas which would have historically been the
subject of philosophy. These include Psychology,
Anthropology
and Science.
Western philosophy
The history of Western
philosophy is often divided into three periods: Ancient
philosophy, Medieval
philosophy, and Modern
philosophy. For a map with the dates and places of birth of
most western philosophers see
here.
Ancient philosophy
Ancient philosophy is the philosophy of the Graeco-Roman world from the fifth century B.C. to the fourth century A.D. It is usually divided into four periods: the pre-Socratic period, the periods of Plato and Aristotle, and the post-Aristotelian period (or Hellenistic period). Sometimes a fifth period is added that includes the Christian and Neo-Platonist philosophers. The most important of the ancient philosophers (in terms of subsequent influence) are Plato and Aristotle.The themes of ancient philosophy are:
understanding the fundamental causes and principles of the universe; explaining it in an
economical and uniform way; the epistemological problem of
reconciling the diversity and change of the natural universe, with
the possibility of obtaining fixed and certain knowledge about it;
questions about that which cannot be percieved with the senses, or
which is an abstraction, for example numbers, elements,
universals, and
gods; the analysis of
patterns of reasoning
and argument; the nature of the good
life and the importance of understanding and knowledge in order
to pursue it; the explication of the concept of justice, and its relation to
various political
systems.
In this period the crucial features of the
philosophical
method were established: a critical approach to received or
established views, and the appeal to reason and
argumentation.
Medieval philosophy
Medieval philosophy is the philosophy of Western Europe and the Middle East during what is now known as the medieval era or the Middle Ages, roughly extending from the fall of the Roman Empire to the Renaissance. Medieval philosophy is defined partly by the rediscovery and further development of classical Greek and Hellenistic philosophy, and partly by the need to address theological problems and to integrate sacred doctrine (in Islam, Judaism and Christianity) with secular learning.Some problems discussed throughout this period
are the relation of faith
to reason, the existence
and unity of God, the object of
theology and metaphysics, the problems of
knowledge, of universals, and of individuation.
Philosophers from the Middle Ages include the
Muslim philosophers Alkindus, Alfarabi,
Alhacen,
Avicenna,
Algazel,
Avempace,
Abubacer and
Averroes;
the Jewish philosophers Maimonides and
Gersonides; and
the Christian philosophers Anselm, Peter
Abelard, Roger Bacon,
Thomas
Aquinas, Duns Scotus,
William
of Ockham and Jean
Buridan.
Early modern philosophy (c. 1600 – c. 1800)
The early modern period is usually considered to begin with the revival of skepticism and with the growth of modern physical science. The main themes of this era are: the problem of how we can know anything about the world outside our own minds; the dispute between rationalists and empiricists, rationalists holding that the ultimate source of knowledge is reason, empiricists, that any genuine knowledge must be justified by experience; the nature of the mind or self, and its relation to the body, and the closely related problem of reconciling our belief in free will with the emerging scientific picture of the physical universe as deterministic; attempts to explain the relationship between God and science, and the rebirth of political philosophy.Important figures include Montaigne,
Descartes,
Francis
Bacon, Locke,
Spinoza,
Leibniz,
Berkeley,
Hume,
and Kant.
Chronologically, this era spans the 17th and 18th centuries, and is
generally considered to end with Kant's systematic
attempt to reconcile Newtonian physics with traditional
metaphysical topics.
Later modern philosophy (c. 1800 – c. 1960)
Later modern philosophy is usually considered to begin after the philosophy of Immanuel Kant at the beginning of the 19th-century. German idealists, such as Fichte, Hegel, and Schelling, expanded on the work of Kant by maintaining that the world is constituted by a rational mind-like process, and as such is entirely knowable.Rejecting idealism, other philosophers, many
working from outside the university, initiated lines of thought
that would occupy academic philosophy in the early and mid-20th
century:
- Peirce and William James initiated the school of pragmatism
- Husserl initiated the school of phenomenology
- Kierkegaard and Nietzsche laid the groundwork for existentialism
- Frege's work in logic and Sidgwick's work in ethics provided the tools for early analytic philosophy
Contemporary philosophy (c. 1960 – present)
In the last hundred years, philosophy has increasingly become an activity practiced within the modern research university, and accordingly it has grown more specialized and more distinct from the natural sciences. Much of philosophy in this period concerns itself with explaining the relation between the theories of the natural sciences and the ideas of the humanities or common sense.It is arguable that later modern philosophy ended
with contemporary philosophy's shift of focus from 19th century
philosophers to 20th century philosophers. Philosophers such as
Heidegger,
the later Wittgenstein,
and Dewey,
occupied philosophical discourses exemplified in thinkers such as
Derrida,
Quine,
Kripke, and
Rorty.
Eastern philosophy
Many societies have considered philosophical questions and built philosophical traditions based upon each other's works. Eastern and Middle Eastern philosophical traditions have influenced Western philosophers. Russian (which to many people still counts as Western), Jewish, Islamic, African, and recently Latin American philosophical traditions have contributed to, or been influenced by, Western philosophy: yet each has retained a distinctive identity.The differences between traditions are often well
captured by consideration of their favored historical philosophers,
and varying stress on ideas, procedural styles, or written
language. The subject matter and dialogues of each can be studied
using methods derived from the others, and there are significant
commonalities and exchanges between them.
Eastern
philosophy refers to the broad traditions that originated or
were popular in India, Persia, China, Korea, Japan, and to an
extent, the Middle East
(which overlaps with Western philosophy due to the spread of the
Abrahamic
religions and the continuing intellectual traffic between these
societies and Europe.)
Babylonian philosophy
- Further information: Babylonian literature: Philosophy
The origins of Babylonian
philosophy can be traced back to the wisdom of early Mesopotamia,
which embodied certain philosophies of life, particularly ethics, in the forms of dialectic, dialogs, epic poetry,
folklore, hymns, lyrics, prose, and proverbs. The reasoning and rationality of the Babylonians
developed beyond empirical
observation.
It is possible that Babylonian philosophy had an
influence on early Greek
philosophy, and later Hellenistic
philosophy. The Babylonian text Dialog of Pessimism contains
similarities to the agonistic thought of the
sophists,
the Heraclitean
doctrine of contrasts, and the dialogs of Plato, as well as a
precursor to the maieutic Socratic
method of Socrates and
Plato.
Chinese philosophy
Philosophy has had a tremendous effect on Chinese civilization, and East Asia as a whole. Many of the great philosophical schools were formulated during the Spring and Autumn Period and Warring States Period, and came to be known as the Hundred Schools of Thought. The four most influential of these were Confucianism, Taoism, Mohism, and Legalism. Later on, during the Tang Dynasty, Buddhism from India also became a prominent philosophical and religious discipline. (It should be noted that Eastern thought, unlike Western philosophy, did not express a clear distinction between philosophy and religion.) Like Western philosophy, Chinese philosophy covers a broad and complex range of thought, possessing a multitude of schools that address every branch and subject area of philosophy.Indian philosophy
In the history of the Indian subcontinent, following the establishment of an Aryan–Vedic culture, the development of philosophical and religious thought over a period of two millennia gave rise to what came to be called the six schools of astika, or orthodox, Indian or Hindu philosophy. These schools have come to be synonymous with the greater religion of Hinduism, which was a development of the early Vedic religion.Hindu philosophy constitutes an integral part of
the culture of Southern Asia,
and is the first of the Dharmic
philosophies which were influential throughout the Far East. The
great diversity in thought and practice of Hinduism is nurtured by
its liberal universalism.
Persian philosophy
Persian philosophy can be traced back as far as Old Iranian philosophical traditions and thoughts, with their ancient Indo-Iranian roots. These were considerably influenced by Zarathustra's teachings. Throughout Iranian history and due to remarkable political and social influences such as the Macedonian, the Arab, and the Mongol invasions of Persia, a wide spectrum of schools of thought arose. These espoused a variety of views on philosophical questions, extending from Old Iranian and mainly Zoroastrianism-influenced traditions to schools appearing in the late pre-Islamic era, such as Manicheism and Mazdakism, as well as various post-Islamic schools. Iranian philosophy after Arab invasion of Persia is characterized by different interactions with the Old Iranian philosophy, the Greek philosophy and with the development of Islamic philosophy. The Illumination school and the Transcendent theosophy are regarded as two of the main philosophical traditions of that era in Persia.African philosophy
Philosophical traditions, such as African philosophy, are rarely studied by foreign academia. Since emphasis is mainly placed on Western philosophy as a reference point, the study, preservation and dissemination of valuable, but lesser known, non-Western philosophical works face many obstacles. Key African philosophers include the Fulani Usman Dan Fodio, founder of the Sokoto Caliphate of Northern Nigeria and Umar Tall of Senegal; both were prolific Islamic scholars. Another African philosopher worthy of note in the pre-colonial period was Anton Wilhelm Amo http://www.kirjasto.sci.fi/amo.htm. In the post-colonial period, different images of what could be argued as "African" Philosophy from the level of epistemology have risen. These could include the thoughts and enquiries of such individuals as Cheik Anta Diop, Francis Ohanyido, CL Momoh, and Chinweizu. http://www.npi.ucla.edu/qualquant/definition.htmThe philosophy of the modern and contemporary
African world, including the diaspora, is often known as Africana
Philosophy. Key philosophers include Frantz
Fanon, Kwesi Wiredu, Paget Henry,
Lewis
Gordon, Mabogo Percy More and many others.
Philosophical doctrines
Realism and nominalism
Realism sometimes means the position opposed to the 18th-century Idealism, namely that some things have real existence outside the mind. Classically, however, realism is the doctrine that abstract entities corresponding to universal terms like 'man' have a real existence. It is opposed to nominalism, the view that abstract or universal terms are words only, or denote mental states such as ideas, beliefs, or intentions. The latter position, famously held by William of Ockham, is conceptualism.Rationalism and empiricism
Rationalism is any view emphasizing the role or importance of human reason. Extreme rationalism tries to base all knowledge on reason alone. Rationalism typically starts from premises that cannot coherently be denied, then attempts by logical steps to deduce every possible object of knowledge.The first rationalist, in this broad sense, is
often held to be Parmenides (fl.
480 BCE), who argued that it is impossible to doubt that thinking
actually occurs. But thinking must have an object, therefore
something beyond thinking really exists. Parmenides deduced that
what really exists must have certain properties – for
example, that it cannot come into existence or cease to exist, that
it is a coherent whole, that it remains the same eternally (in
fact, exists altogether outside time). Zeno of
Elea (born c. 489 BCE) was a disciple of Parmenides, and argued
that motion is impossible, since the assertion that it exists
implies a contradiction.
Plato (427–347 BCE)
was also influenced by Parmenides, but combined rationalism with a
form of realism.
The philosopher's work is to consider being, and the essence of
things. But the characteristic of essences is that they are
universal. The nature of a man, a triangle, a tree, applies to all
men, all triangles, all trees. Plato argued that these essences are
mind-independent 'forms', that humans (but particularly
philosophers) can come to know by reason, and by ignoring the
distractions of sense-perception.
Modern rationalism begins with Descartes.
Reflection on the nature of perceptual experience, as well as
scientific discoveries in physiology and optics, led Descartes (and
also Locke) to the
view that we are directly aware of ideas, rather than objects. This
view gave rise to three questions:
- Is an idea a true copy of the real thing that it represents? Sensation is not a direct interaction between bodily objects and our sense, but is a physiological process involving representation (for example, an image on the retina). Locke thought that a 'secondary quality' such as a sensation of green could in no way resemble the arrangement of particles in matter that go to produce this sensation, although he thought that 'primary qualities' such as shape, size, number, were really in objects.
- How can physical objects such as chairs and tables, or even physiological processes in the brain, give rise to mental items such as ideas? This is part of what became known as the mind-body problem.
- If all the contents of awareness are ideas, how can we know that anything exists apart from ideas?
Descartes tried to address the last problem by
reason. He began, echoing Parmenides, with a principle that he
thought could not coherently be denied: I think, therefore I am
(often given in his original Latin: Cogito ergo
sum). From this principle, Descartes went on to construct a
complete system of knowledge (which involves proving the existence
of God, using, among other means, a version of the ontological
argument). His view that reason alone could yield substantial
truths about reality strongly influenced those philosophers usually
considered modern rationalists (such as Baruch
Spinoza, Gottfried
Leibniz, and
Christian Wolff), while provoking criticism from other
philosophers who have retrospectively come to be grouped together
as empiricists.
Empiricism, in
contrast to rationalism, downplays or dismisses the ability of
reason alone to yield knowledge of the world, preferring to base
any knowledge we have on our senses. John Locke propounded the
classic empiricist view in
An Essay Concerning Human Understanding in 1689, developing a
form of naturalism
and empiricism on
roughly scientific (and Newtonian) principles.
During this era, religious ideas played a mixed
role in the struggles that preoccupied secular philosophy. Bishop
Berkeley's famous idealist
refutation of key tenets of Isaac Newton
is a case of an Enlightenment philosopher who drew substantially
from religious ideas. Other influential religious thinkers of the
time include Blaise
Pascal, Joseph
Butler, and
Jonathan Edwards. Other major writers, such as Jean-Jacques
Rousseau and Edmund
Burke, took a rather different path. The restricted interests
of many of the philosophers of the time foreshadow the separation
and specialization of different areas of philosophy that would
occur in the 20th century.
Skepticism
Skepticism is a philosophical attitude that questions the possibility of obtaining any sort of knowledge. It was first articulated by Pyrrho, who believed that everything could be doubted except appearances. Sextus Empiricus (2nd century CE) describes skepticism as an "ability to place in antithesis, in any manner whatever, appearances and judgments, and thus […] to come first of all to a suspension of judgment and then to mental tranquility." Skepticism so conceived is not merely the use of doubt, but is the use of doubt for a particular end: a calmness of the soul, or ataraxia. Skepticism poses itself as a challenge to dogmatism, whose adherents think they have found the truth.Sextus noted that the reliability of perception
may be questioned, because it is idiosyncratic to the perceiver.
The appearance of individual things changes depending on whether
they are in a group: for example, the shavings of a goat's horn are
white when taken alone, yet the intact horn is black. A pencil,
when viewed lengthwise, looks like a stick; but when examined at
the tip, it looks merely like a circle.
Skepticism was revived in the early modern period
by Michel
de Montaigne and Blaise
Pascal. Its most extreme exponent, however, was David Hume.
Hume argued that there are only two kinds of reasoning: what he
called probable and demonstrative (cf Hume's fork).
Neither of these two forms of reasoning can lead us to a reasonable
belief in the continued existence of an external world.
Demonstrative reasoning cannot do this, because demonstration (that
is, deductive
reasoning from well-founded premises) alone cannot establish
the uniformity of nature (as captured by scientific laws and
principles, for example). Such reason alone cannot establish that
the future will resemble the past. We have certain beliefs about
the world (that the sun will rise tomorrow, for example), but these
beliefs are the product of habit and custom, and do not depend on
any sort of logical inferences from what is already given certain.
But probable reasoning (inductive
reasoning), which aims to take us from the observed to the
unobserved, cannot do this either: it also depends on the
uniformity of nature, and this supposed uniformity cannot be
proved, without circularity, by any appeal to uniformity. The best
that either sort of reasoning can accomplish is conditional truth:
if certain assumptions are true, then certain conclusions follow.
So nothing about the world can be established with certainty. Hume
concludes that there is no solution to the skeptical
argument – except, in effect, to ignore it.
Even if these matters were resolved in every
case, we would have in turn to justify our standard of
justification, leading to an infinite
regress (hence the term regress skepticism).
Many philosophers have questioned the value of
such skeptical arguments. The question of whether we can achieve
knowledge of the external world is based on how high a standard we
set for the justification of such knowledge. If our standard is
absolute certainty, then we cannot progress beyond the existence of
mental sensations. We cannot even deduce the existence of a
coherent or continuing "I" that experiences these sensations, much
less the existence of an external world. On the other hand, if our
standard is too low, then we admit follies and illusions into our
body of knowledge. This argument against absolute skepticism
asserts that the practical philosopher must move beyond solipsism, and accept a
standard for knowledge that is high but not absolute.
Idealism
Idealism is the epistemological doctrine that nothing can be directly known outside of the minds of thinking beings. Or in an alternative stronger form, it is the metaphysical doctrine that nothing exists apart from minds and the "contents" of minds. In modern Western philosophy, the epistemological doctrine begins as a core tenet of Descartes – that what is in the mind is known more reliably than what is known through the senses. The first prominent modern Western idealist in the metaphysical sense was George Berkeley. Berkeley argued that there is no deep distinction between mental states, such as feeling pain, and the ideas about so-called "external" things, that appear to us through the senses. There is no real distinction, in this view, between certain sensations of heat and light that we experience, which lead us to believe in the external existence of a fire, and the fire itself. Those sensations are all there is to fire. Berkeley expressed this with the Latin formula esse est percipi: to be is to be perceived. In this view the opinion, "strangely prevailing upon men", that houses, mountains, and rivers have an existence independent of their perception by a thinking being is false.Forms of idealism were prevalent in philosophy
from the 18th century to the early 20th century. Transcendental
idealism, advocated by Immanuel
Kant, is the view that there are limits on what can be
understood, since there is much that cannot be brought under the
conditions of objective judgment. Kant wrote his Critique
of Pure Reason (1781–1787) in an attempt to reconcile the
conflicting approaches of rationalism and empiricism, and to
establish a new groundwork for studying metaphysics. Kant's
intention with this work was to look at what we know and then
consider what must be true about it, as a logical consequence of,
the way we know it. One major theme was that there are fundamental
features of reality that escape our direct knowledge because of the
natural limits of the human faculties. Although Kant held that
objective knowledge of the world required the mind to impose a
conceptual
or categorical
framework on the
stream of pure sensory data – a framework including space
and time themselves – he maintained that
things-in-themselves existed independently of our perceptions and
judgments; he was therefore not an idealist in any simple sense.
Indeed, Kant's account of things-in-themselves is both
controversial and highly complex. Continuing his work, Johann
Gottlieb Fichte and
Friedrich Schelling dispensed with belief in the independent
existence of the world, and created a thoroughgoing idealist
philosophy.
The most notable work of this German
idealism was
G.W.F. Hegel's Phenomenology
of Spirit, of 1807. Hegel admitted his ideas weren't new, but
that all the previous philosophies had been incomplete. His goal
was to correctly finish their job. Hegel asserts that the twin aims
of philosophy are to account for the contradictions apparent in
human experience (which arise, for instance, out of the supposed
contradictions between "being" and "not being" ), and also
simultaneously to resolve and preserve these contradictions by
showing their compatibility at a higher level of examination
("being" and "not being" are resolved with "becoming") . This
program of acceptance and reconciliation of contradictions is known
as the "Hegelian dialectic". Philosophers in
the Hegelian tradition include Ludwig
Andreas Feuerbach, who coined the term projection as pertaining
to our inability to recognize anything in the external world
without projecting qualities of ourselves upon those things,
Karl
Marx, Friedrich
Engels, and the British
idealists, notably T.H. Green,
J.M.E.
McTaggart, and F.H.
Bradley.
Few 20th century philosophers have embraced
idealism. However, quite a few have embraced Hegelian dialectic.
Immanuel Kant's "Copernican Turn" also remains an important
philosophical concept today.
Pragmatism
main InstrumentalismPragmatism was founded in the spirit of finding a
scientific concept of truth, which is not dependent on either
personal insight (or revelation) or reference to some metaphysical
realm. The truth of a statement should be judged by the effect it
has on our actions and truth should be seen as that which the whole
of scientific enquiry will ultimately agree on. This should
probably be seen as a guiding principle more than a definition of
what it means for something to be true, though the details of how
this principle should be interpreted have been subject to
discussion since Peirce first conceived it. Like Rorty many seem
convinced that Pragmatism holds that the truth of beliefs does not
consist in their correspondence with reality, but in their
usefulness and efficacy.
The late 19th-century American philosophers
Charles
Peirce and William
James were its co-founders, and it was later developed by
John
Dewey as instrumentalism. Since
the usefulness of any belief at any time might be contingent on
circumstance, Peirce and James conceptualised final truth as that
which would be established only by the future, final settlement of
all opinion. Critics have accused pragmatism of falling victim to a
simple fallacy: because something that is true proves useful, that
usefulness is the basis for its truth. Thinkers in the pragmatist
tradition have included John Dewey, George
Santayana, W.V.O. Quine
and C.I.
Lewis. Pragmatism has more recently been taken in new
directions by Richard
Rorty, John Lachs,
Donald
Davidson and Hilary
Putnam.
Phenomenology
Edmund Husserl's phenomenology was an ambitious attempt to lay the foundations for an account of the structure of conscious experience in general. An important part of Husserl's phenomenological project was to show that all conscious acts are directed at or about objective content, a feature that Husserl called intentionality.In the first part of his two-volume work, the
Logical Investigations (1901), he launched an extended attack on
psychologism. In
the second part, he began to develop the technique of descriptive
phenomenology, with the aim of showing how objective judgments are
indeed grounded in conscious experience – not, however, in
the first-person experience of particular individuals, but in the
properties essential to any experiences of the kind in
question.
He also attempted to identify the essential
properties of any act of meaning. He developed the method further
in Ideas (1913) as transcendental phenomenology, proposing to
ground actual experience, and thus all fields of human knowledge,
in the structure of consciousness of an ideal, or transcendental,
ego. Later, he attempted to reconcile his transcendental standpoint
with an acknowledgement of the intersubjective life-world in
which real individual subjects interact. Husserl published only a
few works in his lifetime, which treat phenomenology mainly in
abstract methodological terms; but he left an enormous quantity of
unpublished concrete analyses.
Husserl's work was immediately influential in
Germany, with the foundation of phenomenological schools in Munich
and Göttingen. Phenomenology later achieved international fame
through the work of such philosophers as Martin
Heidegger (formerly Husserl's research assistant), Maurice
Merleau-Ponty, and Jean-Paul
Sartre. Indeed, through the work of Heidegger and Sartre,
Husserl's focus on subjective experience influenced aspects of
existentialism.
Existentialism
Although they didn't use the term, the nineteenth century philosophers Søren Kierkegaard and Friedrich Nietzsche are widely regarded as the fathers of existentialism. Their influence, however, has extended beyond existentialist thought.The main target of Kierkegaard's writings was the
idealist philosophical system of Hegel which, he
thought, ignored or excluded the inner subjective life of living
human beings. Kierkegaard, conversely, held that "truth is
subjectivity", arguing that what is most important to an actual
human being are questions dealing with an individual's inner
relationship to existence. In particular, Kierkegaard, a Christian,
believed that the truth of religious faith was a subjective
question, and one to be wrestled with passionately.
Although Kierkegaard and Nietzsche were among his
influences, the extent to which the German philosopher Martin
Heidegger should be considered an existentialist is debatable.
In Being and
Time he presented a method of rooting philosophical
explanations in human existence (Dasein) to be analysed in terms of
existential categories (existentiale); and this has led many
commentators to treat him as an important figure in the
existentialist movement. However, in The Letter on Humanism,
Heidegger explicitly rejected the existentialism of Jean-Paul
Sartre.
Sartre became the best-known proponent of
existentialism, exploring it not only in theoretical works such as
Being
and Nothingness , but also in plays and novels. Sartre, along
with Albert Camus
and Simone
de Beauvoir, all represented an avowedly atheistic branch of
existentialism, which is now more closely associated with their
ideas of nausea, contingency, bad faith, and the absurd than with
Kierkegaard's spiritual angst. Nevertheless, the focus on the
individual human being, responsible before the universe for the
authenticity of his or her existence, is common to all these
thinkers.
Structuralism and post-structuralism
Inaugurated by the linguist Ferdinand de Saussure, structuralism sought to ferret out the underlying systems through analysing the discourses they both limit and make possible. Saussure conceived of the sign as being delimited by all the other signs in the system, and ideas as being incapable of existence prior to linguistic structure, which articulates thought. This led continental thought away from humanism, and toward what was termed the decentering of man: language is no longer spoken by man to express a true inner self, but language speaks man.Structuralism sought the province of a hard
science, but its positivism soon came under fire by
poststructuralism, a wide field of thinkers, some of whom were once
themselves structuralists, but later came to criticize it.
Structuralists believed they could analyse systems from an
external, objective standing, for example, but the
poststructuralists argued that this is incorrect, that one cannot
transcend structures and thus analysis is itself determined by what
it examines, that systems are ultimately self-referential.
Furthermore, while the distinction between the signifier and
signified was treated as crystalline by structuralists,
poststructuralists asserted that every attempt to grasp the
signified would simply result in the proliferation of more
signifiers, so meaning is always in a state of being deferred,
making an ultimate interpretation impossible.
Structuralism came to dominate continental
philosophy from the 1960s onward, encompassing thinkers as diverse
as Michel
Foucault and Jacques
Lacan.
The analytic tradition
The term analytic philosophy roughly designates a
group of philosophical methods that stress detailed argumentation,
attention to semantics, use of classical logic and non-classical
logics and clarity of meaning above all other criteria. Michael
Dummett in his Origins of Analytical Philosophy makes the case
for counting Gottlob
Frege The Foundations of Arithmetic as the first analytic work,
on the grounds that in that book Frege took the linguistic turn,
analysing philosophical problems through language. Bertrand
Russell and G.E. Moore are
also often counted as founders of analytic philosophy, beginning
with their rejection of British idealism, their defense of realism
and the emphasis they laid on the legitimacy of analysis. Russell's
classic works The Principles of Mathematics, On Denoting
and Principia
Mathematica, aside from greatly promoting the use of classical
first order logic in philosophy, set the ground for much of the
research program in the early stages of the analytic tradition,
emphasising such problems as: the reference of proper names,
whether existence is a property, the meaning of propositions, the
analysis of definite descriptions, the discussions on the
foundations of mathematics; as well as exploring issues of
metaphysical commitment and even metaphysical problems regarding
time, the nature of matter, mind, persistence and change, which
Russell tackled often with the aid of mathematical logic. The
philosophy developed as a critique of Hegel and his
followers in particular, and of grand systems of speculative
philosophy in general, though by no means all analytic
philosophers reject the philosophy of Hegel (see Charles
Taylor) nor speculative philosophy. Some schools in the group
include logical
atomism, logical
positivism, and
ordinary language. The motivation behind the work of analytic
philosophers has been varied. Some have held that philosophical
problems arise through misuse of language or because of
misunderstandings of the logic of our language, while some maintain
that there are genuine philosophical problems and that philosophy
is continuous with science.
In 1921, Ludwig
Wittgenstein published his
Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, which gave a rigidly "logical"
account of linguistic and philosophical issues. At the time, he
understood most of the problems of philosophy as mere puzzles of
language, which could be solved by investigating and then minding
the logical structure of language. Years later he would reverse a
number of the positions he had set out in the Tractatus, in for
example his second major work, Philosophical
Investigations (1953). Investigations was influential in the
development of "ordinary language philosophy", which was promoted
by Gilbert
Ryle, J.L. Austin,
and a few others. In the United States, meanwhile, the philosophy
of W. V. O.
Quine was having a major influence, with such classics as
Two
Dogmas of Empiricism. In that paper Quine criticizes the
distinction between analytic and synthetic statements, arguing that
a clear conception of analyticity is unattainable. He argued for
holism, the thesis that language, including scientific language, is
a set of interconnected sentences, none of which can be verified on
its own, rather, the sentences in the language depend on each other
for their meaning and truth conditions. A consequence of Quine's
approach is that language as a whole has only a very thin relation
to experience, some sentences which refer directly to experience
might me somewhat modified by sense impressions, but as the whole
of language is theory-laden, for the whole language to be modified,
more than this is required. However, most of the linguistic
structure can in principle be revised, even logic, in order to
better model the world. Notable students of Quine include Donald
Davidson and Daniel
Dennett. The former devised a program for giving a semantics to
natural language and thereby answer the philosophical conundrum
'what is meaning?'. A crucial part of the program was the use of
Alfred
Tarski's semantic theory of truth. Dummett, among others,
argued that truth conditions should be dispensed with in the theory
of meaning, and replaced by assertibility conditions. Some
propositions, on this view, are neither true nor false, and thus
such a theory of meaning entails a rejection of the law of the
excluded middle. This, for Dummett, entails antirealism, as Russell
himself pointed out in An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth.
By the 1970s there was a renewed interest in many
traditional philosophical problems by the younger generations of
analytic philosophers. David Lewis,
Saul
Kripke, Derek Parfit
and others took an interest in traditional metaphysical problems,
which they began exploring by the use of logic and philosophy of
language. Among those problems some distinguished ones were: free
will, essentialism, the nature of personal identity, identity over
time, the nature of the mind, the nature of causal laws,
space-time, the properties of material beings, modality, etc. In
those universities where analytic philosophy has spread, these
problems are still being discussed passionately. Analytic
philosophers are now also interested in the methodology of analytic
philosophy itself, with Timothy
Williamson, Wykeham Professor of Logic at Oxford, publishing
recently a book entitled The Philosophy of Philosophy. Some notable
figures in contemporary analytic philosophy are: Timothy
Williamson, Theodore
Sider, John
Hawthorne, Alvin
Goldman, Peter van
Inwagen, Graham
Priest, Scott
Soames, Nathan
Salmon and, of course, Saul Kripke,
who is currently lecturing at CUNY. Analytic philosophy has
sometimes being accused of not contributing to the political debate
or to traditional questions in aesthetics, however, with the
appearance of A
Theory of Justice by John Rawls and
Anarchy, State and Utopia by Robert
Nozick, analytic political philosophy acquired respectability.
Analytic philosophers have also showed depth in their
investigations of aesthetics, with Roger
Scruton, Richard Wollheim, Jerome Levinson and others
developing the subject to its current shape.
Ethics and political
Human nature and political legitimacy
From ancient times, and well beyond them, the roots of justification for political authority were inescapably tied to outlooks on human nature. In The Republic, Plato declared that the ideal society would be run by a council of philosopher-kings, since those best at philosophy are best able to realize the good. Even Plato, however, required philosophers to make their way in the world for many years before beginning their rule at the age of fifty. For Aristotle, humans are political animals (i.e. social animals), and governments are set up in order to pursue good for the community. Aristotle reasoned that, since the state (polis) was the highest form of community, it has the purpose of pursuing the highest good. Aristotle viewed political power as the result of natural inequalities in skill and virtue. Because of these differences, he favored an aristocracy of the able and virtuous. For Aristotle, the person cannot be complete unless he or she lives in a community. His The Nicomachean Ethics and The Politics are meant to be read in that order. The first book addresses virtues (or "excellences") in the person as a citizen; the second addresses the proper form of government to ensure that citizens will be virtuous, and therefore complete. Both books deal with the essential role of justice in civic life.Nicolas of
Cusa rekindled Platonic thought in the early 15th century. He
promoted democracy in Medieval Europe, both in his writings and in
his organization of the Council of Florence. Unlike Aristotle and
the Hobbesian tradition to follow, Cusa saw human beings as equal
and divine (that is, made in God's image), so democracy would be
the only just form of government. Cusa's views are credited by some
as sparking the Italian Renaissance, which gave rise to the notion
of "Nation-States".
Later, Niccolò
Machiavelli rejected the views of Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas
as unrealistic. The ideal sovereign is not the embodiment of the
moral virtues; rather the sovereign does whatever is successful and
necessary, rather than what is morally praiseworthy. Thomas
Hobbes also contested many elements of Aristotle's views. For
Hobbes, human nature is essentially anti-social: people are
essentially egoistic, and this egoism makes life difficult in the
natural state of things. Moreover, Hobbes argued, though people may
have natural inequalities, these are trivial, since no particular
talents or virtues that people may have will make them safe from
harm inflicted by others. For these reasons, Hobbes concluded that
the state arises from a common agreement to raise the community out
of the state of
nature. This can only be done by the establishment of a
sovereign,
in which (or whom) is vested complete control over the community,
and which is able to inspire awe and terror in its subjects.
Many in the Enlightenment were unsatisfied with
existing doctrines in political philosophy, which seemed to
marginalize or neglect the possibility of a democratic state.
David
Hume was among the first philosophers to question the existence
of God, circa 1700. Jean-Jacques
Rousseau was among those who attempted to overturn these
doctrines: he responded to Hobbes by claiming that a human is by
nature a kind of "noble
savage", and that society and social contracts corrupt this
nature. Another critic was John Locke. In
Second Treatise on Government he agreed with Hobbes that the
nation-state was an efficient tool for raising humanity out of a
deplorable state, but he argued that the sovereign might become an
abominable institution compared to the relatively benign
unmodulated state of nature.
Following the doctrine of the fact-value
distinction, due in part to the influence of David Hume and
his student Adam Smith,
appeals to human nature for political justification were weakened.
Nevertheless, many political philosophers, especially moral
realists, still make use of some essential human nature as a
basis for their arguments.
Consequentialism, deontology, and the aretaic turn
One debate that has commanded the attention of ethicists in the modern era has been between consequentialism (actions are to be morally evaluated solely by their consequences) and deontology (actions are to be morally evaluated solely by consideration of agents' duties, the rights of those whom the action concerns, or both).Jeremy
Bentham and John
Stuart Mill are famous for propagating utilitarianism, which is
the idea that the fundamental moral rule is to strive toward the
"greatest happiness for the greatest number". However, in promoting
this idea they also necessarily promoted the broader doctrine of
consequentialism.
Adopting a position opposed to consequentialism,
Immanuel
Kant argued that moral principles were simply products of
reason. Kant believed that the incorporation of consequences into
moral deliberation was a deep mistake, since it would deny the
necessity of practical maxims in governing the working of the will.
According to Kant, reason requires that we conform our actions to
the categorical
imperative, which is an absolute duty. An important
20th-century deontologist, W.D. Ross, has
argued for weaker forms of duties called prima
facie duties.
More recent works have emphasized the role of
character in ethics, a movement known as the aretaic turn
(that is, the turn towards virtues). One strain of this movement
followed the work of Bernard
Williams. Williams noted that rigid forms of both
consequentialism and deontology demanded that people behave
impartially. This, Williams argued, requires that people abandon
their personal projects, and hence their personal integrity, in order to be
considered moral.
G.E.M.
Anscombe, in an influential paper, "Modern Moral Philosophy"
(1958), revived virtue
ethics as an alternative to what was seen as the entrenched
positions of Kantianism and consequentialism. Aretaic perspectives
have been inspired in part by research of ancient conceptions of
virtue. For example, Aristotle's
ethics demands that people follow the Aristotelian mean, or
balance between two vices; and Confucian ethics
argues that virtue consists largely in striving for harmony with
other people. Virtue ethics in general has since gained many
adherents, and has been defended by such philosophers as Philippa
Foot, Alasdair
MacIntyre, and Rosalind
Hursthouse.
Applied philosophy
The thoughts a society thinks have profound repercussions on what it does. The applied study of philosophy yields applications such as those in ethics – applied ethics in particular – and political philosophy. The political and economic philosophies of Confucius, Sun Zi, Ibn Khaldun, Ibn Rushd, Ibn Taimiyyah, Niccolò Machiavelli, Gottfried Leibniz, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Karl Marx, John Stuart Mill, Mahatma Gandhi, Martin Luther King Jr. and others – all of these have been used to shape and justify governments and their actions.In the field of philosophy
of education, progressive education as championed by John Dewey has
had a profound impact on educational practices in the United
States in the 20th century. Descendants of this movement
include the current efforts in philosophy for children. Carl
von Clausewitz's political philosophy
of war has had a profound effect on statecraft,
international
politics, and military
strategy in the 20th century, especially in the years around
World
War II. Logic has become crucially important in mathematics, linguistics, psychology, computer
science, and computer
engineering.
Other important applications can be found in
epistemology, which
aid in understanding the requisites for knowledge, sound evidence,
and justified belief (important in law, economics, decision
theory, and a number of other disciplines). The philosophy
of science discusses the underpinnings of the scientific
method and has affected the nature of scientific investigation
and argumentation. This has profound impacts. For example, the
strictly empirical approach of Skinner's behaviourism affected for
decades the approach of the American psychological establishment.
Deep
ecology and animal
rights examine the moral situation of humans as occupants of a
world that has non-human occupants to consider also. Aesthetics can
help to interpret discussions of music, literature, the plastic
arts, and the whole artistic dimension of life. In general, the
various philosophies strive to provide practical activities with a
deeper understanding of the theoretical or conceptual underpinnings
of their fields.
Often philosophy is seen as an investigation into
an area not sufficiently well understood to be its own branch of
knowledge. What were once philosophical pursuits have evolved into
the modern day fields such as psychology, sociology, linguistics, and economics, for example. But as
such areas of intellectual endeavour proliferate and expand, so
will the broader philosophical questions that they generate.
The
New York Times reported an increase in philosophy majors at
United
States universities in 2008.
References
Further reading
Introductions
- Appiah, Kwame Anthony. Thinking it Through – An Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy, 2003, ISBN 0-19-513458-3
- Blumenau, Ralph. Philosophy and Living. ISBN 0-907845-33-9
- Craig, Edward. Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. ISBN 0-19-285421-6
- Curley, Edwin, A Spinoza Reader, Princeton, 1994, ISBN 0-691-00067-0
- Durant, Will, Story of Philosophy: The Lives and Opinions of the World's Greatest Philosophers, Pocket, 1991, ISBN 0671739166, ISBN 978-0671739164
- Harrison-Barbet, Anthony, Mastering Philosophy. ISBN 0-333-69343-4
- Higgins, Kathleen M. and Solomon, Robert C. A Short History of Philosophy. ISBN 0-19-510196-0
- Russell, Bertrand. The Problems of Philosophy. ISBN 0-19-511552-X
- Sinclair, Alistair J. What is Philosophy? An Introduction. ISBN 0-19-0376594-3 ISBN-13: 978-1903765944
- Sober, E. (2001). Core Questions in Philosophy: A Text with Readings. Upper Saddle River, Prentice Hall. ISBN 0-13-189869-8
- Solomon, Robert C. Big Questions: A Short Introduction to Philosophy. ISBN 0-534-16708-X
- Warburton, Nigel. Philosophy: The Basics. ISBN 0-415-14694-1
Topical introductions
- Copleston, Frederick. Philosophy in Russia: From Herzen to Lenin and Berdyaev. ISBN 0-268-01569-4
- Critchley, Simon. Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. ISBN 0-19-285359-7
- Hamilton, Sue. Indian Philosophy: a Very Short Introduction. ISBN 0-19-285374-0
- Harwood, Sterling, ed., Business as Ethical and Business as Usual (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 2000); www.sterlingharwood.com
- Imbo, Samuel Oluoch. An Introduction to African Philosophy. ISBN 0-8476-8841-0
- Knight, Kelvin. Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre. ISBN 0-7456-1977-0
- Kupperman, Joel J. Classic Asian Philosophy: A Guide to the Essential Texts. ISBN 0-19-513335-8
- Leaman, Oliver. A Brief Introduction to Islamic Philosophy. ISBN 0-7456-1960-6
- Lee, Joe and Powell, Jim. Eastern Philosophy For Beginners. ISBN 0-86316-282-7
- Nagel, Thomas. What Does It All Mean? A Very Short Introduction to Philosophy. ISBN 0-19-505292-7
- Scruton, Roger. A Short History of Modern Philosophy. ISBN 0-415-26763-3
- Smart, Ninian. World Philosophies. ISBN 0-415-22852-2
- Tarnas, Richard. The Passion of the Western Mind: Understanding the Ideas That Have Shaped Our World View. ISBN 0-345-36809-6
Anthologies
- Classics of Philosophy (Vols. 1 & 2, 2nd edition) by Louis P. Pojman
- Classics of Philosophy: The 20th Century (Vol. 3) by Louis P. Pojman
- The English Philosophers from Bacon to Mill by Edwin Arthur
- European Philosophers from Descartes to Nietzsche by Monroe Beardsley
- Contemporary Analytic Philosophy: Core Readings by James Baillie
- Existentialism: Basic Writings (Second Edition) by Charles Guignon, Derk Pereboom
- The Phenomenology Reader by Dermot Moran, Timothy Mooney
- Medieval Islamic Philosophical Writings edited by Muhammad Ali Khalidi
- A Source Book in Indian Philosophy by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan, Charles A. Moore
- A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy by Wing-tsit Chan
- Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, Ed. (1999). Metaphysics: An Anthology. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies. Oxford, Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
- The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (2004) edited by Robert Kane
- Husserl, Edmund and Welton, Donn, The Essential Husserl: Basic Writings in Transcendental Phenomenology, Indiana University Press, 1999, ISBN 0-253-21273-1
Reference works
- The Oxford Companion to Philosophy edited by Ted Honderich
- The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy by Robert Audi
- The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (10 vols.) edited by Edward Craig, Luciano Floridi (available online by subscription); or
- The Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy edited by Edward Craig (an abridgement)
- Encyclopedia of Philosophy (8 vols.) edited by Paul Edwards; in 1996, a ninth supplemental volume appeared which updated the classic 1967 encyclopedia.
- Routledge History of Philosophy (10 vols.) edited by John Marenbon
- History of Philosophy (9 vols.) by Frederick Copleston
- A History of Western Philosophy (5 vols.) by W. T. Jones
- Encyclopaedia of Indian Philosophies (8 vols.), edited by Karl H. Potter et al. (first 6 volumes out of print)
- Indian Philosophy (2 vols.) by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan
- A History of Indian Philosophy (5 vols.) by Surendranath Dasgupta
- History of Chinese Philosophy (2 vols.) by Fung Yu-lan, Derk Bodde
- Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy edited by Antonio S. Cua
- Encyclopedia of Eastern Philosophy and Religion by Ingrid Fischer-Schreiber, Franz-Karl Ehrhard, Kurt Friedrichs
- Companion Encyclopedia of Asian Philosophy by Brian Carr, Indira Mahalingam
- A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English by John A. Grimes
- History of Islamic Philosophy edited by Seyyed Hossein Nasr, Oliver Leaman
- History of Jewish Philosophy edited by Daniel H. Frank, Oliver Leaman
- A History of Russian Philosophy: From the Tenth to the Twentieth Centuries by Valerii Aleksandrovich Kuvakin
- Ayer, A. J. et al., Ed. (1994) A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations. Blackwell Reference Oxford. Oxford, Basil Blackwell Ltd.
- Blackburn, S., Ed. (1996)The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
- Mauter, T., Ed. The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy. London, Penguin Books.
- Runes, D., Ed. (1942). The Dictionary of Philosophy. New York, The Philosophical Library, Inc.
- Angeles, P. A., Ed. (1992). The Harper Collins Dictionary of Philosophy. New York, Harper Perennial.
- Bunnin, N. et al., Ed. (1996) The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy. Blackwell Companions to Philosophy. Oxford, Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
- Popkin, R. H. (1999). The Columbia History of Western Philosophy. New York, Columbia University Press.
philosophy in Afrikaans: Filosofie
philosophy in Amharic: ፍልስፍና
philosophy in Old English (ca. 450-1100):
Ūðwitegung
philosophy in Arabic: فلسفة
philosophy in Aragonese: Filosofía
philosophy in Aromanian: Filosofia
philosophy in Assamese: দৰ্শন
philosophy in Asturian: Filosofía
philosophy in Aymara: Lup'intawi
philosophy in Azerbaijani: Fəlsəfə
philosophy in Bengali: দর্শন
philosophy in Min Nan: Tiat-ha̍k
philosophy in Belarusian: Філасофія
philosophy in Belarusian (Tarashkevitsa):
Філасофія
philosophy in Bavarian: Philosophie
philosophy in Bosnian: Filozofija
philosophy in Breton: Prederouriezh
philosophy in Bulgarian: Философия
philosophy in Catalan: Filosofia
philosophy in Chuvash: Философи
philosophy in Cebuano: Pilosopiya
philosophy in Czech: Filosofie
philosophy in Corsican: Filosofia
philosophy in Welsh: Athroniaeth
philosophy in Danish: Filosofi
philosophy in German: Philosophie
philosophy in Estonian: Filosoofia
philosophy in Modern Greek (1453-):
Φιλοσοφία
philosophy in Spanish: Filosofía
philosophy in Esperanto: Filozofio
philosophy in Basque: Filosofia
philosophy in Persian: فلسفه
philosophy in Faroese: Heimspeki
philosophy in French: Philosophie
philosophy in Western Frisian: Filosofy
philosophy in Friulian: Filosofie
philosophy in Irish: Fealsúnacht
philosophy in Scottish Gaelic:
Feallsanachd
philosophy in Galician: Filosofía
philosophy in Hakka Chinese: Chet-ho̍k
philosophy in Korean: 철학
philosophy in Armenian: Փիլիսոփայություն
philosophy in Hindi: दर्शन
philosophy in Croatian: Filozofija
philosophy in Ido: Filozofio
philosophy in Iloko: Filosofia
philosophy in Indonesian: Filsafat
philosophy in Interlingua (International
Auxiliary Language Association): Philosophia
philosophy in Inuktitut:
ᐃᓱᒪᓕᐅᕐᓂᖅ/isumaliurniq
philosophy in Icelandic: Heimspeki
philosophy in Italian: Filosofia
philosophy in Hebrew: פילוסופיה
philosophy in Javanese: Filsafat
philosophy in Kannada: ತತ್ತ್ವಶಾಸ್ತ್ರ
philosophy in Georgian: ფილოსოფია
philosophy in Kashubian: Filozofijô
philosophy in Kirghiz: Философия
philosophy in Haitian: Filozofi
philosophy in Kurdish: Felsefe
philosophy in Ladino: Filosofiya
philosophy in Lao: ປັດຊະຍາ
philosophy in Latin: Philosophia
philosophy in Latvian: Filozofija
philosophy in Luxembourgish: Philosophie
philosophy in Lithuanian: Filosofija
philosophy in Limburgan: Filosofie
philosophy in Lojban: pijyske
philosophy in Lombard: Filusufía
philosophy in Hungarian: Filozófia
philosophy in Macedonian: Философија
philosophy in Malayalam: തത്ത്വശാസ്ത്രം
philosophy in Marathi: तत्त्वज्ञान
philosophy in Mazanderani: فلسفه
philosophy in Malay (macrolanguage):
Falsafah
philosophy in Mongolian: Философи
philosophy in Dutch: Filosofie
philosophy in Dutch Low Saxon: Filesefie
philosophy in Newari: दर्शन
philosophy in Japanese: 哲学
philosophy in Norwegian: Filosofi
philosophy in Norwegian Nynorsk: Filosofi
philosophy in Narom: Philosophie
philosophy in Novial: Filosofia
philosophy in Occitan (post 1500):
Filosofia
philosophy in Uzbek: Falsafa
philosophy in Papiamento: Filosofia
philosophy in Pushto: فلسفه
philosophy in Polish: Filozofia
philosophy in Portuguese: Filosofia
philosophy in Romanian: Filozofie
philosophy in Quechua: Yachay wayllukuy
philosophy in Russian: Философия
philosophy in Sardinian: Filosofia
philosophy in Scots: Philosophy
philosophy in Southern Sotho: Filosofi
philosophy in Albanian: Filozofia
philosophy in Sicilian: Filusufìa
philosophy in Simple English: Philosophy
philosophy in Slovak: Filozofia
philosophy in Slovenian: Filozofija
philosophy in Serbian: Филозофија
philosophy in Serbo-Croatian: Filozofija
philosophy in Sundanese: Filsafat
philosophy in Finnish: Filosofia
philosophy in Swedish: Filosofi
philosophy in Tagalog: Pilosopiya
philosophy in Tamil: மெய்யியல்
philosophy in Kabyle: Tafelsuft
philosophy in Tatar: Fälsäfä
philosophy in Thai: ปรัชญา
philosophy in Vietnamese: Triết học
philosophy in Tajik: Фалсафа
philosophy in Tok Pisin: Pilosopi
philosophy in Cherokee: ᎤᏬᎳᏨᎯ
philosophy in Turkish: Felsefe
philosophy in Ukrainian: Філософія
philosophy in Urdu: فلسفہ
philosophy in Venetian: Fiłoxofìa
philosophy in Volapük: Filosop
philosophy in Võro: Filosoofia
philosophy in Walloon: Filozofeye
philosophy in Wolof: Xeltu
philosophy in Yiddish: פילאזאפיע
philosophy in Contenese: 哲學
philosophy in Dimli: Filozofi
philosophy in Zeeuws: Filosofie
philosophy in Samogitian: Fėluosuopėjė
philosophy in Chinese: 哲学
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
Aristotelianism,
Berkeleianism,
Bradleianism,
Buddha-like composure, Cynicism, Cyrenaic hedonism,
Cyrenaicism,
Epicureanism,
Fichteanism,
Hegelianism,
Heideggerianism,
Heracliteanism,
Herbartianism,
Humism, Kantianism, Leibnizianism, Marxism, Mimamsa, Neo-Hegelianism,
Neo-Pythagoreanism, Neoplatonism, Newtonian
physics, Oriental calm, Peripateticism, Platonism, Purva Mimamsa,
Pyrrhonism, Pythagoreanism, Sankhya, Schellingism, Scotism, Socratism, Sophism, Sophistry, Spencerianism, Stoicism, Thomism, Weltanschauung, acosmism, acoustics, aerophysics, aesthetics, agnosticism, animalism, animatism, animism, aplomb, applied physics, astrophysics, atomism, attitude, basic conductor
physics, biophysics,
body of ideas, calm disposition, calm of mind, calmness, chemical physics,
composure, control, cool, coolheadedness, coolness, cosmotheism, countenance, criticism, cryogenics, crystallography,
cytophysics,
deduction, deductive
reasoning, deism, demonstration, dialectical
materialism, discourse, discourse of
reason, discursive reason, dispassion, dualism, easy mind, eclecticism, egoism, electron physics,
electronics,
electrophysics,
empiricism, epistemology, equanimity, ethics, ethos, eudaemonism, existentialism, feeling, geophysics, hedonism, humanism, hylomorphism, hylotheism, hylozoism, icy calm, idea, idealism, ideology, immaterialism, imperturbability,
imperturbation,
indisturbance,
individualism,
induction, inductive
reasoning, intuitionism, logic, logical thought, macrophysics, materialism, mathematical
physics, mechanics,
mechanism, medicophysics, mental
composure, mentalism,
metaphysics,
microphysics,
monism, mysticism, natural philosophy,
natural science, naturalism, neocriticism, nominalism, notion, nuclear physics, ontologism, ontology, opinion, optics, optimism, organic mechanism,
organicism, outlook, panpsychism, pantheism, patience, peace of mind,
peacefulness,
pessimism, philosophic
composure, philosophicalness,
physic, physical
chemistry, physical science, physicalism, physicism, physicochemistry,
physicomathematics,
physics, placidity, pluralism, point of view,
positivism, pragmaticism, pragmatism, proof, psychism, psychological
hedonism, psychophysics, quiet, quiet mind, quietude, radiation physics,
radionics, ratiocination, rationalism, rationality, rationalization,
rationalizing,
realism, reason, reasonableness, reasoning, resignation, restraint, sang-froid,
sangfroid, secular
humanism, self-control, self-possession, semiotic, semiotics, sensationalism, sentiment, serenity, skepticism, solar physics,
solid-state physics, soothingness, sophistry, specious reasoning,
statics, stereophysics, stoicism, substantialism, sweet
reason, syncretism,
system of ideas, system of theories, tenets, theism, theoretical physics,
thermodynamics,
thinking, thoughtfulness, tranquillity, transcendentalism,
unruffledness,
utilitarianism,
viewpoint, voluntarism, world view,
zoophysics