Dictionary Definition
perfect adj
1 being complete of its kind and without defect
or blemish; "a perfect circle"; "a perfect reproduction"; "perfect
happiness"; "perfect manners"; "a perfect specimen"; "a perfect
day" [ant: imperfect]
2 without qualification; used informally as
(often pejorative) intensifiers; "an arrant fool"; "a complete
coward"; "a consummate fool"; "a double-dyed villain"; "gross
negligence"; "a perfect idiot"; "pure folly"; "what a sodding
mess"; "stark staring mad"; "a thoroughgoing villain"; "utter
nonsense" [syn: arrant(a),
complete(a),
consummate(a),
double-dyed(a),
everlasting(a),
gross(a),
perfect(a),
pure(a),
sodding(a),
stark(a),
staring(a),
thoroughgoing(a),
utter(a)]
3 precisely accurate or exact; "perfect timing" n
: a tense of verbs used in describing action that has been
completed (sometimes regarded as perfective aspect) [syn: perfective, perfective
tense, perfect
tense] v : make perfect or complete; "perfect your French in
Paris!" [syn: hone]
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Etymology
From perfit, from parfit (modern: parfait), from perfectus, perfect passive participle of perficere, to finish, from per-, through, thorough, + facere, to do, to makePronunciation 1
Adjective
- Fitting its definition precisely.
- a perfect circle
- Having all of its parts in harmony with a common purpose.
- That bucket with the hole in the bottom is a poor bucket, but it is perfect for watering plants.
- Thoroughly skilled or talented.
- practice makes perfect
- Excellent and delightful in all respects.
- a perfect day
- (of a tense or verb form) Representing a completed action.
- Sexually mature and fully differentiated.
- Having both male (stamens) and female (carpels) parts.
Synonyms
- (fitting its definition precisely): accurate, flawless
- (thoroughly skilled or talented): expert, proficient
- (biology: sexually mature and fully differentiated): mature
- (botany: having both male and female parts): bisexual, hermaphroditic
Synonyms to be checked
Antonyms
- (botany: having both male and female parts): imperfect
Derived terms
Related terms
Translations
fitting its definition precisely
- Bulgarian: съвършен, съвършена, съвършено
- Chinese: 完美 (wánměi)
- Czech: dokonalý
- Dutch: perfect, perfecte
- Finnish: täydellinen
- French: parfait, parfaite
- German: perfekt, vollkommen
- Italian: perfetto, perfetta
- Japanese: (, kanpekina)
- Polish: doskonały, perfekcyjny
- Romanian: perfect
- Slovene: popoln , popolna , popolno
- Swedish: fullkomlig, fulländad, perfekt
having all of its parts in harmony with a common
purpose
thoroughly skilled or talented
- Czech: dokonalý
- Swedish: fullkomlig, fulländad, perfekt
excellent and delightful in all respects
grammar: of a tense or verb form: representing a
completed action
- Dutch: voltooid, voltooide
- Finnish: perfektinen, perfekti-
- French: parfait, parfaite
- Japanese: (, kanryō no)
- Romanian: perfectul simplu
- Swedish: perfekt
biology: sexually mature and fully
differentiated
botany: having both male and female parts
- Finnish: kaksineuvoinen, täydellinen
- ttbc Chinese: 完善 (wán shàn)
- ttbc Ido: perfekta
- ttbc Polish: (1,2) doskonały , doskonała , doskonałe n, f plural, doskonali p
- ttbc Spanish: perfecto
Pronunciation 2
Verb
Related terms
Translations
make perfect
- Dutch: perfectioneren
- Finnish: tehdä täydelliseksi
- German: vollenden, perfektionieren
- Italian: perfezionare
- Romanian: perfecta
- Slovene: izpopolniti
- Spanish: perfeccionar
- Swedish: finslipa, fullkomna, fullända, förbättra, förfina, göra perfekt
Romanian
Etymology
lang=la, lang=dePronunciation
Adjective
- , flawless
Declension
Antonyms
Adverb
Noun
- (perfect simplu) preterite tense, simple perfect
- (perfect compus) compound perfect tense
Extensive Definition
Perfection is, broadly, a state of completeness
and flawlessness.
The term "perfection" is
actually used to designate a range of diverse, if often kindred,
concepts. These concepts
have historically been addressed in a number of discrete disciplines,
notably mathematics,
physics, chemistry, ethics, aesthetics, ontology and theology.
The term and the concept
The form of the word long fluctuated in various
languages. The English
language had the alternates, "perfection" and the Biblical
"perfectness."
The word, "perfection" derives from the Latin "perfectio",
and "perfect" — from "perfectus."
These expressions in turn come from "perficio" — "to
finish", "to bring to an end." "Perfectio(n)" thus literally means
"a finishing", and "perfect(us)" — "finished", much as in grammatical parlance ("perfect
tense").
Many modern languages have adopted their terms
for the concept of "perfection" from the Latin: the French
"parfait" and
"perfection"; the Italian
"perfetto" and
"perfezione";
the English
"perfect" and "perfection"; the Russian
"совершенный"
(sovyershenniy); the Croatian
"dovershiti"; the Czech
"dokonalost"; the Slovak
"dokonaly" and "dokonalost"; the Polish
"doskonały" and "doskonałość."
The genealogy of the concept of "perfection"
reaches back beyond Latin, to Greek. The
Greek equivalent of the Latin "perfectus" was "teleos." The latter
Greek expression generally had concrete referents, such as a
perfect physician or flutist, a perfect comedy or a perfect social
system. Hence the Greek "teleiotes" was not yet so fraught with
abstract and superlative associations as would be the Latin
"perfectio" or the modern "perfection." To avoid the latter
associations, the Greek term has generally been translated as
"completeness"
rather than "perfection." The oldest definition of "perfection",
fairly precise and distinguishing the shades of the concept, goes
back to Aristotle. In
Book Delta of the Metaphysics, he distinguishes three meanings of
the term, or rather three shades of one meaning, but in any case
three different concepts. That is perfect:
1. which is complete — which contains all the
requisite parts;
2. which is so good that nothing of the kind
could be better;
3. which has attained its purpose. The first of
these concepts is fairly well subsumed within the second. Between
those two and the third, however, there arises a duality in
concept. This duality was expressed by Thomas
Aquinas, in the Summa
Theologiae, when he distinguished a twofold perfection: when a
thing is perfect in itself — as he put it, in its substance; and
when it perfectly serves its purpose. The variants on the concept
of perfection would have been quite of a piece for two thousand
years, had they not been confused with other, kindred concepts. The
chief of these was the concept of that which is the best: in Latin,
"excellentia" ("excellence"). In antiquity,
"excellentia" and "perfectio" made a pair; thus, for example,
dignitaries were called "perfectissime", just as they are now
called "excellency." Nevertheless, these two expression of high
regard differ fundamentally: "excellentia" is a distinction among
many, and implies comparison; while "perfectio" involves no
comparison, and if something is deemed perfect, then it is deemed
so in itself, without comparison to other things. Gottfried
Wilhelm Leibniz, who thought much about perfection and held the
world to be the best of
possible worlds, did not claim that it was perfect.
Paradoxes
The parallel existence of two concepts of perfection, one strict ("perfection", as such) and the other loose ("excellence"), has given rise — perhaps since antiquity but certainly since the Renaissance — to a singular paradox: that the greatest perfection is imperfection. This was formulated by Lucilio Vanini (ca. 1585 – 1619), who had a precursor in the 16th-century writer Joseph Juste Scaliger, and they in turn referred to the ancient philosopher Empedocles. Their argument, as given by the first two, was that if the world were perfect, it could not improve and so would lack "true perfection", which depends on progress. To Aristotle, "perfect" meant "complete" ("nothing to add or subtract"). To Empedocles, according to Vanini, perfection depends on incompleteness ("perfectio propter imperfectionem"), since the latter possesses a potential for development and for complementing with new characteristics ("perfectio complementii"). This view relates to the baroque esthetic of Vanini and Marin Mersenne: the perfection of an art work consists in its forcing the recipient to be active — to complement the art work by an effort of mind and imagination.The paradox of perfection — that
imperfection is perfect — applies not only to human affairs, but to
technology. Thus,
irregularity in
semiconductor
crystals (an
imperfection, in the form of contaminants) is requisite
for the production of semiconductors. The solution to the apparent
paradox lies in a distinction between two concepts of "perfection":
that of regularity,
and that of utility.
Imperfection is perfect in technology, in the sense that
irregularity is useful.
Perfect numbers
"Perfect numbers" have been distinguished ever since the ancient Greeks called them "teleioi." There was, however, no consensus among the Greeks as to which numbers were "perfect" or why. A view that was shared by Plato held that 10 was a perfect number. Mathematicians, including the mathematician-philosopher Pythagoreans, proposed as a perfect number, the number 6.The number 10 was thought perfect because there
are 10 fingers to the two hands. The number 6 was believed perfect
for being divisible in a special way: a sixth part of that number
constitutes unity; a third is two; a half — three; two-thirds
(Greek:
dimoiron) is four; five-sixths (pentamoiron) is five; six is the
perfect whole. The ancients also considered 6 a perfect
number because the human foot constituted one-sixth the height
of a man, hence the number 6 determined the height of the human
body.
Thus both numbers, 6 and 10, were credited with
perfection, both on purely mathematical grounds and on grounds of
their relevance in nature.
Belief in the "perfection" of certain numbers
survived antiquity,
but this quality came to be ascribed to other numbers as well. The
perfection of the number 3 actually became proverbial: "omne trinum
perfectum" (Latin: "all threes
are perfect"). Another number, 7, found a devotee in the sixth-century
Pope Gregory I
(Gregory the Great), who favored it on grounds similar to those of
the Greek mathematicians who had seen 6 as a perfect
number, and in addition for some reason he associated the
number 7 with the concept of "eternity."
The Middle Ages,
however, championed the perfection of 6: Augustine
and Alcuin
wrote that God
had created the world in 6 days because that was the perfect
number.
The Greek mathematicians had regarded as perfect
that number which equals the sum of its divisors that are smaller than
itself. Such a number is neither 3 nor 7 nor 10, but 6, for 1 + 2 +
3 = 6. But there are more numbers that show this property, such as
28, which = 1 + 2 + 4 + 7 + 14. It became customary to call such
numbers "perfect." Euclid gave a
formula for (even) "perfect" numbers:
- Nn = 2n−1 (2n − 1)
Despite over 2,000 years of study, it still is
not known whether there exist infinitely many perfect numbers; or
whether there are any odd ones.
Today the term "perfect
number" is merely historic in nature, used for the sake of
tradition. These peculiar numbers had received the name on account
of their analogy to the construction of man, who was held to be
nature's most perfect
creation, and above all on account of their own peculiar regularity. Thus, they had
been so named on the same grounds as perfect objects in nature, and
perfectly proportioned edifices and statues created by man; the
numbers had come to be called "perfect" in order to emphasize their
special regularity.
The Greek mathematicians had named
these numbers "perfect" in the same sense in which philosophers and artists used the word. Jamblich
(In Nicomachi arithmeticam, Leipzig, 1894) states that the Pythagoreans
had called the number 6 "marriage", "health", and "beauty", on
account of the harmony
and accord of that number.
The perfect
numbers early on came to be treated as the measure of other
numbers: those in which the sum of the divisors is greater than the
number itself, as in 12, have — since as early as Theon of
Smyrna, ca. 130 A.D. — been called "redundant"
(Latin:
redundantio) or "more than perfect" (plus quam perfecti), and those
the sum of whose divisors is smaller, as in 8, have been called
"deficient"
(deficientes).
Currently 44 perfect
numbers have been identified.
Physics and chemistry
A variety of physical and chemical concepts include, in their names, the word "perfect."The physicist designates as a perfectly
rigid body, one that "is not deformed by forces applied to it."
He uses the concept in the full awareness that this is a fictitious
body, that no such body exists in nature. The concept is an
ideal
construct.
A perfectly
plastic body is one that is deformed infinitely at a constant
load corresponding to the body's limit of plasticity: this is a
physical model,
not a body observed in nature.
A perfectly
black body would be one that absorbed completely, radiation
falling upon it — that is, a body with a coefficient of absorption
equal to unity.
A crystal is perfect when its
physically equivalent walls are equally developed; it has a perfect
structure when it
answers the requirements of spatial symmetry and is free of
structural defects, dislocation, lacunae and other flaws.
A perfect
fluid is one that is incompressible and non-viscous — this,
again, is an ideal fluid
that does not exist in nature. A perfect gas
is one whose molecules do not interact with each other and which
have no volume of their own. Such a gas is fictitious, just as are
perfectly solid, perfectly rigid, perfectly plastic and perfectly
black bodies. They are termed "perfect" in the strict
(non-metaphorical) sense of the word. These are all concepts that
are necessary in physics, insofar as they are limiting, ideal,
fictitious — insofar as they set the extreme which nature may at
the most approach.
In a looser sense, real things are called
"perfect" if they approximate perfection more or less closely,
though they be not, strictly speaking, perfect.
The relation of these perfect bodies to real
bodies may be illustrated by the relation of a perfect gas to a
real one. The equation of state of a perfect gas is a first
approximation to a quantum equation of state that results from
statistical physics. Thus, the equation of state of a real gas
within classical limits assumes the form of the equation of state
of a perfect gas. That is, the equation of state of a perfect gas
describes an ideal gas (comprising points, that is, dimensionless
molecules that do not act upon one another).
The perfect gas
equation arose from the work of Robert
Boyle, Edme
Mariotte and Joseph
Louis Gay-Lussac, who, in studying the properties of real gases,
found formulas
applicable not to these but to an ideal, perfect
gas.
Ethics
The ethical question of perfection concerns not whether man is perfect, but whether he should be. And if he should be, then how is this to be attained?Plato seldom actually
used the term, "perfection"; but the concept of "good",
central to his philosophy, was tantamount to "perfection." He
believed that approximation to the idea of perfection makes people
perfect.
Soon after, the Stoics introduced
the concept of perfection into ethics expressly, describing it as
harmony — with nature, reason, man himself. They held
that such harmony — such perfection — was attainable for
anyone.
Plato and the Stoics had made perfection a
philosophical
watchword. Soon it would be transformed, in Christianity,
into a religious
one.
The Christian doctrine of perfection rests on
Gospel.
Matthew 5:48
enjoins: "Be ye therefore perfect, even as your Father which is in
heaven is perfect." Luke says the
same, only replacing "perfect" with "merciful" (evidently, for
Matthew, an attribute of perfection). Early Christian writings,
especially Paul's,
are replete with calls to perfection. Many of these are collected
in a discourse by St.
Augustine, De perfectione iustitiae hominis. They begin already
with the Old
Testament: "Thou shalt be perfect with the Lord thy God."
(Deuteronomy
18:13.) Elsewhere, synonyms for "perfection" are
"undefiled", "without rebuke", "without blemish", "blameless",
"holy", "righteous", "unblamable", "unreprovable."
Augustine explains that not only that man is
properly termed perfect and without blemish who is already perfect,
but also he who strives unreservedly after perfection. This is a
broader concept, of approximate perfection, resembling that used in
the exact
sciences. The first ancient and Christian perfection was not
very remote from modern self-perfection. St. Ambrose
in fact wrote about degrees of perfection ("gradus piae
perfectionis"). Along with the idea of perfection, Holy
Scripture conveyed doubt as to whether perfection was
attainable for man. According to 1
John 1:8, "If we say that we have no sin, we deceive ourselves,
and the truth is not in us." Similarly Matthew
19:17: "And he said unto him, Why callest thou me good? there is
none good but one, that is, God..." And St. Jerome
wrote: "Perfectio vera in coelestibus" — true perfection is to be
found only in heaven.
As early as the 5th century
C.E., two distinct views on perfection had arisen within the
Church: that it was attainable by man on earth by his own powers;
and, that it may come to pass only by special divine
grace. The first view, which was championed by Pelagius, was
condemned in 417 C.E.; the second view, which was championed by St.
Augustine, prevailed at the very beginning of the 5th century
and became authoritative. Still, the Church did not condemn the
writings of the
Pseudo-Areopagite, purportedly the first bishop of Athens, voicing a
natural possibility for man to rise to perfection, to the
contemplation of God. And so, for centuries, two views contended
within the Church.
Even as, for the ancient philosophers, the
essence of perfection had been harmony, so for the Gospel and the
Christian theologians it was charity,
or love. St. Paul
wrote (Epistle
to the Colossians, 3:14): "And above all these things put on
charity, which is the bond of perfectness." St. Gregory
wrote that perfection will be realized only after the fulfillment
of history — only "then will the world be beautiful and perfect."
Still, everyone should make his own approach to perfection — to
holiness. Discourses in
moral theology and asceticism were generous with
advice on how this was to be done.
The medieval concept of perfection
and self-perfection, especially in its mature form, can be natural
for modern man. As formulated by Peter
Lombard, this concept implies that perfection is a result of
development.
And as described by Aegidius
Romanus, perfection has not only personal sources
("personalia") but social ones ("secundum statum"). Since the
individual is formed within a society, the second perfection
subsumes the first, in accordance with the "order of the universe"
("ordo universi"). The social perfection is binding on man, whereas
personal perfection is only becoming to him. Theses on perfection
persist within the Church to the present day. The first condition
for perfection is the desire of it. Also necessary is grace — but
God gives grace to those who desire perfection and strive for it.
Another condition for perfection is constancy of striving and
effort. Augustine
says: "He who stops, regresses." And effort is necessary in things
not only great but also in the smallest; the Gospel according to
St. Luke
says: "He that is faithful in that which is least is faithful also
in much: and he that is unjust in the least is unjust also in
much." An aid in approaching perfection is an awareness of God's perfection and of
one's own imperfection. The 14th century
saw, with the Scotists, a shift
in interest from moral to
ontological perfection;
the 15th
century, particularly during the Italian
Renaissance, a shift to artistic perfection. The first half
of the 16th century saw John Calvin's
complete conditioning of man's perfection on the grace of
God.
The second half of the 16th century brought the
Counter-reformation,
the Council of
Trent, and a return of the Catholic
concept; and also, heroic attempts to attain perfection through
contemplation and
mortification.
This was the age of Ignatius
Loyola and the founding of the Jesuit
Order; of St.
Teresa of Ávila (1515-82) and St.
John of the Cross (1542-91), and the 1593 founding of the
Barefoot
Carmelites. It was the epitome of the Christian idea
of perfection and remains so to this day. The first half of the
17th century saw attempts at a Catholic reform of the idea of
perfection. This was the time of Cornelis
Jansen (1585-1638) and of Jansenism — of a
growing belief in predestination and in the
impossibility of perfection without grace.
With the second half of the 17th century came a
further development in the doctrine of predestination — the
doctrine of "Quietism."
Perfection could be reached through a passive awaiting of grace
rather than by an active striving. This theory, formulated in
Spain by
Miguel de
Molinos (ca. 1628 - 1697), spread in France, where it was
espoused by Madame Guyon
(1648-1717) and for a time attracted
François de Salignac de la Mothe-Fénelon.
The 18th century brought a sea change to the idea
of moral perfection. Faith in it remained, but it changed character
from religious to
secular. This secular,
18th-century perfection was a fundamental article of faith for the
Enlightenment.
Its central tenet was that nature was perfect; and perfect,
too, was the man who lived in harmony with nature's law. Primitive
man was held to be the most perfect, for he was closest to nature.
Perfection lay behind present-day man rather than before him, for
civilization
distanced man from perfection instead of bringing him closer to
it.
A second interpretation, however, took the
contrary view: civilization perfected man
by bringing him closer to reason, and thereby to nature; for reason would direct
life with due consideration for the laws of
nature.
The former, retrospective view of perfection had
antecedents in antiquity:
Hesiod and
Ovid had
described a "golden age"
that had existed at the beginning of time, and which had been
succeeded by silver, copper and Iron Ages, each inferior to the
previous. The renewal of this view now, after two millennia, was
stimulated by European contact with the "primitive" peoples of the
Americas.
Jean-Jacques
Rousseau was but one of many who wrote in a similar vein. These
two mid-18th-century
schools of thought — one seeing perfection in nature and in the past, and the
other in civilization and in the
future — represented a reaction not against the idea of perfection,
but against its transcendental
interpretation: as, earlier, the measure of perfection had been the
idea of God, so
now it was the idea of nature or of civilization. It was the
latter idea that ultimately gained the upper hand and passed into
the 19th century as the legacy of the Enlightenment.
The idea of perfection as transcendental, fell away; only worldly
perfection counted. The idea that perfection was a matter of grace,
also fell by the wayside; man himself must strive for it, and if a
single man could not accomplish it, then perhaps mankind could. As
God had been
the measure of perfection during the Middle Ages,
so now man was: the measure had become smaller, more accessible. To
the thinking of the 19th century, such worldly, human perfection
might ultimately be attainable by everyone. And if not perfection,
then improvement. This would be the great concept of the modern age. At
the very midpoint of the 18th century, there occurred an
exceptional momentary retreat from the idea of perfection. It was
in the French Encyclopédie.
The entry, "Perfection" (vol. XII, 1765), discussed only technical
perfection, in the sense of the matching of human products to the
tasks set for them; no mention was made of ontological, moral or esthetic perfection.
Otherwise, the 18th century saw great declarations championing the
future perfection of man, as in Immanuel
Kant's Idee zu einer allgemeinem Geschichte (1784) and
Johann Gottfried von Herder's Ideen (1784/91).
Perfection was expected to come about by a
variety of means. Partly it would be by way of natural development
and progress (the view espoused by David Hume)
but more so by way of education (precursors of this
view included John Locke and
David
Hartley, and some fervent exponents included the leaders of the
Polish
Enlightenment) and by way of overt state action (Claude
Adrien Helvétius, later Jeremy
Bentham); reliance was placed in cooperation among people
(Charles
Fourier, 1808), later in eugenics (Francis
Galton, 1869). While the foundations of the faith in the future
perfectibility of man changed, the faith itself persisted. It
linked the people of the Enlightenment
with the idealists and
romantics — with
Johann
Gottlieb Fichte,
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, the Polish
Messianists — as well as with the 19th-century
Positivists and
evolutionists;
Herbert
Spencer penned a great new declaration championing the future
perfection of man. The idea of human perfectibility had, however,
become more comprehensive. Man would attain greater perfection, in
the sense that he would live more rationally, healthily, happily,
comfortably. But there was no adequate term for this new
conception, as the term "perfection" had a moral coloring, while
the new goal was more intellectual, physical and social.
In 1852, John
Henry Newman, the future British
cardinal,
wrote that it would be well if the English
language, like the Greek, had
a term to express intellectual perfection,
analogously to the term "health", which addresses man's
physical state, and to "virtue", which speaks to his
moral nature. During the 19th century, the Germans would come
to call perfection, thus construed, "culture" (Kultur), and the
French would
call it "civilization"
(civilisation). One of the elements of perfection, in its new
construction, is health,
understood by the World
Health Organization as "a state of complete physical and mental
well-being."
Still, the burgeoning achievements of
contemporary biology
have not dislodged the age-old interest in moral perfection — with
the important distinction, that the goal now is not so much
perfection as improvement. A classic early-19th
century exponent of this view was Fichte.
In the 20th and
21st
centuries, the advances of science and technology appear to have
been paralleled to some extent by increasingly pluralistic
attitudes. The Polish philosopher
Władysław Tatarkiewicz (1886-1980) has written: "To demand of
someone that he strive after perfection seems equally inappropriate
as to blame him for not striving after it." Such striving, he adds,
"is often egocentric and yields poorer moral and social results
than an outward-directed behavior based not on self-perfection but
on good will and kindliness toward others."
Aesthetics
The ancient Greeks viewed perfection as a requisite for beauty and high art. The Pythagoreans held that perfection was to be found in the right proportions and in a harmonious arrangement of parts. The idea that beauty and art were characterized by perfection, was subsequently embraced by Plato, who believed that art ought to be "apt, suitable, without deviations" — in short, "perfect."From a conviction that perfection was a single
quality, the Pythagoreans, Plato and their adherents held that
beauty also was a single quality; hence, for every kind of art,
there was but one perfect and proper form. Plutarch stated
(De Musica) that, during the early Greek age, musical harmonies that were recognized
as perfect were legally binding at public performances.
Similarly, in temple architecture from the
5th
century BCE, there were established "orders."
There were established proportions
for Doric
temples, and for Ionic temples.
Likewise in sculpture,
for centuries, it was a matter of dogma that certain proportions of
the human body were perfect and obligatory.
There was also a prevalent belief that certain
shapes and
proportions were in themselves perfect. Plato felt that the
perfect proportion was the ratio of the side to the diagonal of a square.
His authority was so great that architects and other artists
continued using this proportion, even when ignorant of its source,
as late as the Middle Ages.
Another early idea — one that was to be espoused by many
illustrious writers and artists of various periods — found
perfection in the circle
and the sphere. Aristotle wrote
in the Physica that the circle was "the perfect, first, most
beautiful form." Cicero wrote in De
natura deorum (On the Nature of the Gods): "Two forms are the most distinctive: of
solids, the sphere... and of plane
figures, the circle... There is nothing more
commensurate than these
forms."
In a commentary to Aristotle's De coelo et mundo
(On the Heavens and Earth), the medieval Pole, Jan of
Słupcza, wrote: "The most perfect body ought to have the most
perfect form, and such [a body] is heaven, while the most perfect
form is the round form, for nothing can be added to it." In the
famous illustrated Les très riches heures du duc de Berry, paradise is depicted as
contained within an ideal sphere. The Renaissance
architect Sebastiano
Serlio (1475-1554) stated: "the round form is the most perfect
of all."
The most excellent of 16th-century
architects, Andrea
Palladio, held that "the most perfect and most excellent" form
was "the round form, since of all forms it is the simplest, the
most uniform, the strongest, the most capacious" and "is the most
suitable for rendering the unity, infinity, uniformity and
righteousness of God." This was the same thought as in Jan of
Słupcza and in Serlio, and it was one of uncommon durability. The
Middle
Ages — Romanesque
and Gothic
alike — had been quite taken with the idea of perfection. But a
true explosion of the imperative for perfection came with the
Renaissance.
Renaissance aesthetics placed less emphasis than
had classical
aesthetics on the unity of things perfect. Baldassare
Castiglione, in his Courtier,
wrote, of Leonardo,
Andrea
Mantegna, Raphael, Michelangelo
and Giorgione, that
"each of them is unlike the others, but each is the most perfect
[perfectissimus] in his style." The great architect and polymath Leone
Battista Alberti wrote (De architectura) that "the art of
building... in Italy [had] achieved
perfect maturity", that the Romans had
"created such a perfect art of building that there was in it
nothing mysterious, hidden or unclear." This was yet another
formulation of the concept of perfection.
Daniele
Barbaro, in his 1567 translation of Vitruvius,
classically defined perfection as "that which lacks nothing and to
which nothing can be added."
The Renaissance showed a marked concern with
preeminence in perfection. Leonardo concluded that the most perfect
of the arts was painting. In 1546 Benedetto
Varchi compared great masters in the arts. Others compared
art and science, art and nature, and perfection in the
arts of the ancients with that in the modern masters. The 16th
century saw comparisons of their music, the 17th — of
their visual arts
and especially of their poetry. These comparisons
construed perfection fairly loosely; the concept was treated more
strictly by architects. The Renaissance
distinguished a variety of properties to perfection. It was
variously held to be:
- an objective property (Petrarch, who opposed perfection to other esthetic qualities such as grace);
- specific to art rather than to nature (Vasari);
- a rare property (Alberti felt that not even Greek architecture had attained perfection);
- a property of the whole work rather than of its parts (Alberti);
- a conjunction of many values (Lodovico Dolce thought Raphael perfect because Raphael had manifold talent, as opposed to the one-sided Michelangelo);
- something that required not merely talent but art, that is, skill (Vasari);
- not the sole value in a work of art (Vasari differentiated perfection from grace; Renaissance Platonists such as Ficino viewed perfection as a divine attribute).
In the eclectic view of the late
Renaissance, perfection would require uniting the talents of many
artists. The concept of perfection was harder to apply to
Renaissance literature but became so
common — often, linked to "eccelente" — as to become banal. Its
frequent application brought about its relativization and even
subjectivization.
Beginning with Serlio
and Palladio,
perfection in art had become less important, less definite, less
objective. The striving for perfection no longer had the importance
for men of
letters that it did for the great architects. But the 17th
century still revered perfection, as shown by the appearance of
that word in book titles: De perfecta poesi by the Polish poet
Maciej Kazimierz Sarbiewski (1595-1640); Le peintre
parfait (1767
by André
Félibien; and Idée de la perfection de la peinture (1662) by Fréart
de Chambray.
Sarbiewski offered several theses: poetry not
only imitates things perfectissime ("most perfectly"), but imitates
them as they ought perfectissime to be in nature; perfect art is
recognized by its agreement with nature, as well as its
universality; art is the more perfect, the nobler (nobilior) its
manner of representing things; it is the more perfect, the more
truths it contains; perfection has various degrees — it is higher
in poetry than in
prose. In classicism, especially in
French
17th-century
classicism, from an ideal attainable by few, perfection became an
obligation for every author. And inasmuch as the criterion of
perfection had been lowered, "perfection" now meant only
correctness. In the ensuing devaluation, it was not enough that art
be perfecta, it should be perfectissima.
Perfection, formerly the supreme characterization
for a work of art, now became but one of many positive
characterizations. Cesare Ripa,
in his Iconologia (published 1593, but typical for
the 17th century), presented perfezione as a concept of equal
status with grace
(grazia), prettiness
(venustà) and beauty
(bellezza).
Leibniz's pupil,
Christian
Wolff, in his Psychology, wrote that beauty consists in
perfection, and that this was why beauty was a source of pleasure.
No such general esthetic theory, explicitly naming perfection, had
ever been formulated by any of its devotees from Plato to Palladio. Wolff's
theory of beauty-as-perfection was developed by the school's chief
aesthetician,
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten. This tradition remained active
in Germany as late as Gotthold
Ephraim Lessing, who considered both beauty and sublimity to be ideas of
perfection; when unity prevailed, beauty emerged; when plurality — sublimity.
In the latter part of the 18th century, Immanuel
Kant wrote much in his Critique
of Judgment about perfection — inner and outer, objective and
subjective, qualitative and quantitative, perceived clearly and
obscurely, the perfection of nature and that of art. Nevertheless,
in aesthetics Kant found that "The judgment of taste [i.e.,
aesthetic judgment] is entirely independent of the concept of
perfection" — that is, beauty was something different from
perfection. Earlier in the 18th century, France's leading
aesthetician, Denis
Diderot, had questioned whether perfection was a more
comprehensible idea than beauty. Jean-Jacques
Rousseau had treated perfection as an unreal concept, and wrote
Jean
le Rond d'Alembert, "Let us not seek the chimera
of perfection, but that which is the best possible."
In England, in
1757, the
important aesthetician Edmund Burke
denied that perfection was the cause of beauty. Quite the contrary,
he argued that beauty nearly always involved an element of
imperfection; for example, women, in order to heighten their
attractiveness, emphasized their weakness and frailty, which is to
say, their imperfection. The 18th century was the last for which
perfection was a principal concept in aesthetics. In the 19th
century, perfection survived only vestigially as a general
expression of approval. Alfred de
Musset held that "Perfection is no more attainable for us than
is infinity. One ought not to seek it anywhere: not in love, nor
beauty, nor happiness, nor virtue; but one should love it, in order
to be virtuous, beautiful and happy, insofar as that is possible
for man."
In the 20th century, Paul
Valéry wrote: "To strive for perfection, to devote endless time
to a work, to set oneself — like Goethe— an
unattainable goal, are all intents that are precluded by the
pattern of modern life."
The dismissal of the question concerning whether
artists can achieve perfection, still left the question: Do artists
want to achieve it? Is that their actual goal? Some artists,
schools and epochs have aimed for perfection. Others have nurtured
other goals: pluralism, novelty, powerful sensations, faithfulness to
truth, self-expression
and expression
of the world, creativity and originality — all of which
may roughly be summarized as "expression."
There have been ages of perfection, and ages of
expression. The arts of ancient
Greece, the Renaissance and
neoclassicism were
arts of perfection. In the mannerist, baroque and romantic periods, expression
has prevailed.
Ontology and theology
see also Christian perfection The Greek philosopher Anaximander described the world as "endless" (apeiron), Xenophanes — as "the greatest" (megistos). But while they ascribed great qualities to the world, they did not regard it as perfect.Only Parmenides seems
to have considered existence to be "tetelesmenon"
("finished"); and Melissos,
his successor in the Eleatic school,
said that existence "was entirely" ("pan esti"). Thus both saw
perfection in existence; true existence was one, constant,
immutable. Moreover, Parmenides thought the world to be finite,
limited in all directions, and like a sphere — which was a mark of its
perfection.
Parmenides' view was embraced to some extent by
Plato. He
thought that the world was the work of a good Demiurge, and that
this was why order and harmony prevailed in the world. The world
was the best, the most beautiful, perfect. It had a perfect shape
(spherical) and a perfect motion (circular).
But Plato said nothing about the Demiurge
architect-of-the-world himself being perfect. And understandably
so, for perfection implied finitude, limits; whereas it was the
world, not its creator, that had limits. A similar view was held by
Aristotle: the
world could be perfect, but God could not.
Only the pantheist Stoics held the
divinity to be perfect — precisely because they identified it with
the world. Cicero wrote in De
natura deorum (On the Nature of the Gods) that the world
"encompasses... within itself all beings... And what could be more
nonsensical than denying perfection to an all-embracing being...
Besides the world, there is no thing that does not lack something
and that is harmonious, perfect and finished in every respect..."
At a certain moment, Greek philosophy became bound up with the
religion of the Christians:
the abstract concept of first cause
became linked with the religious concept of God; the primum
movens became identified with the Creator,
the absolute with the divine Person. Features of an absolute
existence were discovered in the Person of the Creator: He was
immutable, timeless. And absolute existence took on the attributes
of a person: it was good, omnipotent, omnipresent. Christian
theology united the
features of the first cause
in Aristotle's Metaphysics
with those of the Creator in the Book of
Genesis. But the attributes of God did not include perfection,
for a perfect being must be finite; only of such a being might one
say that it lacked nothing.
There was another reason for the denial, to God,
of perfection — in a branch of Christian theology that was under
the influence of Plotinus. In this
view, the absolute from which the world derived could not be
grasped in terms of human concepts, even the most general
and transcendent. Not only was that absolute not matter, it was not spirit either, nor idea; it was superior to these. It
exceeded any description or praise; it was incomprehensible and
ineffable; it was beyond all that we may imagine — including
perfection. Medieval Christian
philosophy held that the concept of perfection might describe
creation,
but was not appropriate to describe God. The Scholastic,
Thomas
Aquinas, indicating that he was following Aristotle,
defined a perfect thing as one that "possesses that of which, by
its nature, it is capable." Also (Summa
Theologiae): "That is perfect, which lacks nothing of the
perfection proper to it." Thus there were, in the world, things
perfect and imperfect, more perfect and less perfect. God permitted
imperfections in creation when they were necessary for the good of
the whole. And for man it was natural to go by degrees from
imperfection to perfection.
Duns Scotus
understood perfection still more simply and mundanely: "Perfection
is that which it is better to have than not to have." It was not an
attribute of God but a property of creation: all things partook of
it to a greater or lesser degree. A thing's perfection depended on
what sort of perfection it was eligible for. In general, that was
perfect which had attained the fullness of the qualities possible
for it. Hence "whole" and "perfect" meant more or less the same
("totum et perfectum sunt quasi idem"). This was a teleological concept, for it
implied an end
(goal or purpose). God created things that served certain purposes,
created even those purposes, but He himself did not serve any
purpose. Since God was not finite, He could not be called perfect:
for the concept of perfection served to describe finite things.
Perfection was not a theological concept, but an
ontological one,
because it was a feature, in some degree, of every being. The 9th-century
thinker Paschasius
Rodbertus wrote: "Everything is the more perfect, the more it
resembles God." Still, this did not imply that God himself was
perfect. The concept of perfection, as an attribute of God, entered
theology only in modern
times, through René
Descartes — and in the plural, as the "perfections" of
God.
After Descartes, the concept of perfection as a
principal concept in philosophy was upheld by other great 17th-century
thinkers. In Benedict
Spinoza's philosophy, however, there was no personal God, and
perfection became a property of — even a synonym for — the
existence of reality (that is, for the essence of things).
Leibniz wrote: "As
M. Descartes states, existence itself is perfection." Leibniz
added: "Perfection, I call any simple quality, if it is positive
and absolute, such that, if it expresses something, it does so
without limits." At the same time, Leibniz also construed
perfection, in his Monadology, in
an utterly different way: "Only that is perfect which possesses no
limits, that is, only God." This concept would last out the entire
17th century. Subsequently Immanuel
Kant would describe perfection as "omnitudo realitatis" ("the
omnitude of reality"). Thus perfection, which during the Middle Ages
could be a property of any individual being, in 17th-century
philosophy became as well, and indeed preeminently, a property of
God.
Leibniz's pupil and successor, Christian
Wolff, took up this concept of perfection — but with a
difference. Wolff ascribed perfection not to being as a whole, but
once again to its individual constituents. He gave, as examples, an
eye that sees faultlessly, and a watch that runs faultlessly. He
also distinguished variants — perfectio simplex and composita,
primaria and secundaria — and differentiated the magnitude of
perfection (magnitudo perfectionis).
Wolff's pupil,
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, derived perfection from rules,
but anticipated their collisions (regularum collisio) leading to
exceptions (exceptio) and limiting the perfection of things.
Baumgarten distinguished perfection simplex and composita, interna
and externa, transcendentalis and accidentalis; and, positing so
broad a construction, he arrived at the conclusion that "everything
is perfect."
In short, Wolff and his pupils had returned to
the ontological concept
of perfection that the Scholastics had
used. The theological
concept of perfection had lived only from Descartes to Leibniz, in
the 17th century.
Thanks to Wolff's school, the concept of
perfection lasted in Germany through the
18th century. In other western countries, however, especially
France and
Britain,
in that century the concept of perfection was already in decline.
It was ignored by the French Grande
Encyclopédie.
The history of the concept of perfection had
undergone great evolutions — from "Nothing in the world is
perfect", to "Everything is perfect"; and from "Perfection is not
an attribute of God", to "Perfection is an attribute of God."
With Christian
Wolff's school, every thing had become perfect. This was a
singular moment in the history of the ontological concept of
perfection; and soon thereafter, that history came to an end.
One term, many concepts
The foregoing discussion shows that the term "perfection" has been used to designate a variety of concepts.- The word "perfection" has a special meaning in mathematics, where it gives a proper name to certain numbers that demonstrate uncommon properties.
- Elsewhere, the term "perfection" is used consistently with the word's etymology ("perfect" = "finished"). That is perfect which lacks nothing. This is how the term has been used in ontology (a perfect being), ethics (a perfect life) and medicine (perfect health). In these fields, the concept is understood variously as ideal model or as actual approximation to the model.
- Also called "perfect" is that which completely achieves its purpose. Christian Wolff gave examples from biology (perfect vision) and technology (a clock that runs neither slow nor fast). Here "perfection" is less fictitious model than actual approximation to the model.
- That is "perfect", which completely fulfills its functions. In social discourse, one speaks of a perfect artist, engineer or carpenter. The term is used similarly in art criticism, when speaking of perfect technique or of the perfect likeness of a portrait. Here again, "perfection" is either ideal model or approximate realization of the model.
- In aesthetics and art theory, perfection is ascribed to what is fully harmonious — to what is constructed in accordance with a single principle (e.g., the Parthenon, the Odyssey).
Except for the first, mathematical sense, all
these concepts of "perfection" show a kinship, and oscillate
between ideal and approximation.
However, the expression, "perfect", is also used
colloquially — as a
superlative
("perfect idiot", "perfect scoundrel", "perfect storm"). Here,
perfectum is confused with excellens.
Perfection has also been construed as that which
is the best. In theology, when Descartes and
Leibniz
termed God
"perfect", they had in mind something other than model;
than that which lacks nothing; that achieves its purpose; that fulfills its
functions; or that is harmonious.
Notes
References
- Władysław Tatarkiewicz, O doskonałości, Warsaw, Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, 1976. An English translation by Christopher Kasparek, On Perfection, was serialized in Dialectics and Humanism: the Polish Philosophical Quarterly, vol. VI, no. 4 (autumn 1979), pp. 5-10; vol. VII, no. 1 (winter 1980), pp. 77-80; vol. VII, no. 2 (spring 1980), pp. 137-39; vol. VII, no. 3 (summer 1980), pp. 117-24; vol. VII, no. 4 (autumn 1980), pp. 145-53; vol. VIII, no. 1 (winter 1981), pp. 187-92; and vol. VIII, no. 2 (spring 1981), pp. 11-12.
-
- Kasparek's translation has subsequently appeared in the book: Władysław Tatarkiewicz, On perfection, Warsaw University Press, Center of Universalism, 1992, pp. 9-51. The book is a collection of papers by and about the late Professor Tatarkiewicz.
Quotations
- Antoine de Saint-Exupéry is reputed to have said: "Perfection [in design] is achieved, not when there is nothing more to add, but when there is nothing left to take away."
perfect in Arabic: كمال
perfect in German: Vollkommenheit
perfect in French: Perfection
perfect in Italian: Perfezione
perfect in Portuguese: Perfeição
perfect in Albanian: Përsosmëria
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
KO,
OK, absolute, accomplish, accomplished, accurate, achieve, adept, admitting no exception,
adroit, all right,
all-embracing, all-encompassing, all-out, all-pervading, ameliorate, aorist, appropriate, apt, arrant, authentic, beautify, best, better, beyond all praise,
blameless, born, broad-based, button up, call
off, cancel, cap, carry out, carry through, carry
to completion, categorical, chaste, classical, clean, clean up, clear, climax, close out, close up,
complete, comprehensive, conclude, conclusive, congenital, consummate, correct, crass, crown, culminate, cultivate, dead right,
decided, decisive, deep-dyed, defectless, definite, definitive, deft, delete, determinate, develop, dispose of, do to
perfection, downright,
drop the curtain, durative, dyed-in-the-wool,
effect, egregious, elaborate, embellish, emend, end, end off, entire, evolve, exact, exceed, excel, excellent, execute, exhaustive, experienced, expert, explicit, express, expunge, exquisite, extinguish, faultless, final, finalize, finish, finish off, finish up,
finished, fit, fitting, fixed, flagrant, flat, flat-out, flawless, fold up, fulfilled, full, fully realized, future, future perfect, get done,
get it over, get over with, get through, get through with, gifted, give the quietus,
glaring, global, go one better, gross, historical present,
holy, ideal, illimitable, immaculate, impeccable, imperfect, implicit, improve, improve on, inappealable, incomparable, indefectible, indefective, indisputable, infallible, inimitable, intact, integral, intensive, intolerable, irreproachable, just, just right, kayo, kibosh, kill, knock out, letter-perfect,
lifelike, limitless, masterful, masterly, matchless, mature, mere, meticulous, model, mop up, needed, no strings, nonpareil, okay, omnibus, omnipresent, open, out-and-out, outright, outweigh, overbalance, overbear, overcome, overpass, overtop, past, past perfect, peerless, peremptory, perfected, pervasive, plain, plenary, plumb, pluperfect, point tense,
polish, polish off,
polished, positive, precious, precise, predominate, preponderate, present, present perfect,
preterit, prevail, professional, proficient, profound, progressive tense,
pronounced, proper, pure, put paid to, put right,
radical, rank, realize, rectify, refine, regular, reliable, required, requisite, right, righteous, ripen, round, round out, scrag, season, set right, shattering, sheer, shocking, shoot down, simple, sinless, skilled, sleek, slick, smooth, sound, spotless, stainless, stark, stark-staring, straight, straight-out,
straight-up-and-down, sublime, suitable, superb, superlative, supreme, surpass, surpassing, sweeping, taintless, talented, tense, terminate, the veriest,
thorough, thoroughgoing,
through-and-through, top,
top off, top out, total,
tower above, tower over, transcend, true, trump, ubiquitous, unadulterated, unalloyed, unbearable, unblemished, unbound, unbounded, unbroken, uncircumscribed,
unconditional,
unconditioned,
unconfined, unconscionable, uncontaminated, undamaged, undeniable, undiluted, undoubting, unequivocal, unerring, unexcelled, unfaultable, unflawed, unhampered, unhesitating, unimpaired, uninjured, universal, unlimited, unmatched, unmeasured, unmistakable, unmitigated, unmixed, unqualified, unquestioning, unrelieved, unreserved, unrestricted, unspoiled, unspotted, untainted, unwaivable, utter, veritable, very, whole, wholesale, wide-open, wind up,
wipe out, without exception, without reserve, without strings, wrap
up, zap