Dictionary Definition
nonexistent adj
1 not having existence or being or actuality;
"chimeras are nonexistent" [ant: existent]
2 not existing; "innovation has been sadly
lacking"; "character development is missing from the book" [syn:
lacking(p),
missing, wanting(a)]
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Translations
not existent
- Czech: neexistující
- Dutch: niet-bestaand
Extensive Definition
Existence is what is asserted by the verb 'exist'
(derived from the Latin word
'existere', meaning to appear or emerge or stand out). The word
'exist' is certainly agrammatical
predicate, but philosophers have long disputed whether it is
also a logical
predicate.
Some philosophers claim that it predicates
something called 'existence' of the subject. Thus 'four-leaved
clover exists' predicates 'exists' of the subject 'four-leafed
clover'. Cognates for this
predicate are 'is real', 'has being', 'is found in reality', 'is in
the real world' and so on.
Other philosophers have denied that existence is
logically a predicate, and claim that it is merely what is asserted
by the etymologically distinct
verb 'is', and that all statements containing the predicate
'exists' can be reduced to statements that do not use this
predicate. For example, 'Four-leaved clover exists' can be analysed
into the equivalent statement 'some clover is four-leaved', where
the verb 'is' connects the subject 'some clover' with the predicate
'four-leaved'.
This philosophical question is an old one, and
has been discussed and argued over by philosophers from Aristotle,
through Avicenna, Aquinas, Scotus, Hume, Kant, Kierkegaard and
many others.
Historical conceptions
In the western tradition of philosophy, the first comprehensive treatments of the subject are from Plato's Phaedo, Republic, and Statesman and Aristotle's Metaphysics, though earlier fragmentary writing exists. Aristotle developed a complicated theory of being, according to which only individual things, called substances fully have being, but other things such as relations, quantity, time and place (called the categories) have a derivative kind of being, dependent on individual things.The Neo-Platonists
and some early Christian
philosophers argued about whether existence had any reality except
in the mind of God. Some taught that existence was a snare and a
delusion, that the world, the flesh, and the devil existed only to
tempt weak humankind away from God.
The medieval
philosopher Thomas
Aquinas, perhaps following the Persian
philosopher Avicenna, argued
that God is pure being, and that in God essence and existence are the
same. At about the same time, the nominalist philosopher
William
of Ockham, argued, in Book I of his Summa Totius
Logicae (Treatise on all Logic, written some time before 1327)
that Categories are not a form of Being in their own right, but
derivative on the existence of individuals.
Early modern philosophy
The early modern treatment of the subject derives from Antoine Arnauld and Pierre Nicole's Logic, or 'The Art of Thinking', better known as the Port-Royal Logic, first published in 1662. Arnauld thought that a proposition or judgment, consists of taking two different ideas and either putting them together or rejecting them:The two terms are joined by the verb "is" (or "is
not", if the predicate is denied of the subject). Thus every
proposition has three components: the two terms, and the "copula" that connects or
separates them. Even when the proposition has only two words, the
three terms are still there. For example "God loves humanity",
really means "God is a lover of humanity", "God exists" means "God
is a thing".
This theory of judgment dominated logic for
centuries, but it has some obvious difficulties: it only considers
proposition of the form "All A are B.", a form which logicians call
universal.
It does not allow propositions of the form "Some A are B.", a form
logicians call existential.
If neither A nor B includes the idea of existence, then "some A are
B" simply adjoins A to B. Conversely, if A or B do include the idea
of existence in the way that "triangle" contains the idea "three
angles equal to two right angles", then "A exists" is automatically
true, and we have an ontological
proof of A's existence. (Indeed Arnauld's contemporary Descartes
famously argued so, regarding the concept "God" (discourse 4,
Meditation 5)). Arnauld's theory was current until the middle of
the nineteenth century.
David Hume
argued that the claim that a thing exists, when added to our notion
of a thing, does not add anything to the concept. For example, if
we form a complete notion of Moses, and superadd to that notion the
claim that Moses existed, we are not adding anything to the notion
of Moses. Kant also
argued that existence is not a "real" predicate, but gave no
explanation of how this is possible, indeed his famous discussion
of the subject is merely a restatement of Arnauld's doctrine that
in the proposition "God is omnipotent", the verb "is" signifies the
joining or separating of two concepts such as "God" and
"omnipotence".
Existence is often considered as to be "there".
As cited in "The Giver". By Louis Lowry.
Predicative nature
John Stuart Mill (and also Kant's pupil Herbart) argued that the predicative nature of existence was proved by sentences like "A centaur is a poetic fiction" or "A greatest number is impossible" (Herbart). Franz Brentano challenged this, so also (as is better known) did Frege. Brentano argued that we can join the concept represented by a noun phrase "an A" to the concept represented by an adjective "B" to give the concept represented by the noun phrase "a B-A". For example, we can join "a man" to "wise" to give "a wise man". But the noun phrase "a wise man" is not a sentence, whereas "some man is wise" is a sentence. Hence the copula must do more than merely join or separate concepts. Furthermore, adding "exists" to "a wise man", to give the complete sentence "a wise man exists" has the same effect as joining "some man" to "wise" using the copula. So the copula has the same effect as "exists". Brentano argued that every categorical proposition can be translated into an existential one without change in meaning and that the "exists" and "does not exist" of the existential proposition take the place of the copula. He showed this by the following examples:- The categorical proposition "Some man is sick", has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A sick man exists" or "There is a sick man".
- The categorical proposition "No stone is living" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A living stone does not exist" or "there is no living stone".
- The categorical proposition "All men are mortal" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "An immortal man does not exist" or "there is no immortal man".
- The categorical proposition "Some man is not learned" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A non-learned man exists" or "there is a non-learned man".
Frege developed a similar view (though later) in
his great work
The Foundations of Arithmetic, as did Charles
Peirce. The Frege-Brentano view is the basis of the dominant
position in modern
Anglo-American philosophy: that existence is asserted by the
existential quantifier (as expressed by Quine's
slogan "To be is to be the value of a variable." — On
What There Is, 1948).
In Two
Dogmas of Empiricism, Quine says of classes, The issue over there being classes seems more a question of
convenient conceptual scheme; the issue over there being centaurs,
or brick houses on Elm Street, seems more a question of fact. But I
have been urging that this difference is only one of degree, and
that it turns upon our vaguely pragmatic inclination to adjust one
strand of the fabric of science rather than another in
accommodating some particular recalcitrant experience.
Semantics
In mathematical logic, there are two quantifiers, "some" and "all", though as Brentano (1838-1917) pointed out, we can make do with just one quantifier and negation. The first of these quantifiers, "some" is also expressed as "there exists". Thus, in the sentence "There exist a man," the term "man" is asserted to be part of existence. But we can also assert, "There exists a triangle." Is a "triangle", an abstract idea, part of existence in the same way that a "man", a physical body, is part of existence? Do abstractions such as goodness, blindness, and virtue exist in the same sense that chairs, tables, and houses exist? What categories, or kinds of thing can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition?Worse, does "existence" exist?
In some statements, existence is implied without
being mentioned. The statement "A bridge crosses the Thames at
Hammersmith." cannot just be about a bridge, the Thames, and
Hammersmith. It must be about "existence" as well. On the other
hand, the statement "A bridge crosses the Styx at Limbo," has the
same form, but while in the first case we understand a real bridge
in the real world made of stone or brick, what "existence" would
mean in the second case is less clear.
The nominalist approach is to
argue that certain noun phrases can be "eliminated" by rewriting a
sentence in a form that has the same meaning, but which does not
contain the noun phrase. Thus Ockham
argued that "Socrates has wisdom", which apparently asserts the
existence of a reference for "wisdom", can be rewritten as
"Socrates is wise", which contains only the referring phrase
"Socrates". This method became widely accepted in the twentieth
century by the analytic
school of philosophy.
However, this argument may be inverted by
realists in arguing that since the sentence "Socrates is wise"
can be rewritten as "Socrates has wisdom", this proves the
existence of a hidden referent for "wise".
A further problem is that human beings seem to
process information about fictional characters in much the same way
that they process information about real people. For example, in
the 2008 United States presidential election, a politician and
actor named Fred
Thompson ran for the
Republican Party nomination. In polls, potential voters
identified Fred Thompson as a "law and order" candidate. Thompson
plays a fictional character on the television series
Law and Order. There is no doubt that the people who make the
comment are aware that Law and Order is fiction, but at some level,
they process fiction as if it were fact. Another example of this is
the common experience of actresses who play the villain in a soap
opera being accosted in public as if they are to blame for the
actions of the character they play.
A scientist might make a clear distinction about
objects that exist, and assert that all objects that exist are made
up of either matter or energy. But in the layperson's worldview, existence includes
real, fictional, and even contradictory objects. Thus if we reason
from the statement Pegasus flies to
the statement Pegasus exists, we are not asserting that Pegasus is
made up of atoms, but rather that Pegasus exists in a particular
worldview, the worldview of classical myth. When a mathematicians
reasons from the statement "ABC is a triangle" to the statement
"triangles exist", she is not asserting that triangles are made up
of atoms but rather that triangles exist within a particular
mathematical
model.
Modern approaches
According to Bertrand Russell's Theory of Descriptions, the negation operator in a singular sentence takes wide and narrow scope: we distinguish between "some S is not P" (where negation takes "narrow scope") and "it is not the case that 'some S is P'" (where negation takes "wide scope"). The problem with this view is that there appears to be no such scope distinction in the case of proper names. The sentences "Socrates is not bald" and "it is not the case that Socrates is bald" both appear to have the same meaning, and they both appear to assert or presuppose the existence of someone (Socrates) who is not bald, so that negation takes narrow scope.The theory of descriptions has generally fallen
into disrepute, though there have been recent attempts to revive it
by Stephen
Neale and Frank
Jackson. According to the direct-reference
view, an early version of which was originally proposed by Bertrand
Russell, and perhaps earlier by Gottlob
Frege, a proper name strictly has no meaning when there is no
object to which it refers. This view relies on the argument that
the semantic function of a proper name is to tell us which object
bears the name, and thus to identify some object. But no object can
be identified if none exists. Thus, a proper name must have a
bearer if it is to be meaningful.
To adapt an argument of Peter
Strawson's, someone who points to an apparently empty space,
uttering "that's a fine red one" communicates nothing to someone
who cannot see or understand what he is pointing to. Variants of
the direct-reference view have been proposed by Saul Kripke,
Gareth
Evans, Nathan
Salmon, Scott
Soames, and others.
Existence in the wide and narrow senses
According to the "two sense" view of existence, which derives from Alexius Meinong, existential statements fall into two classes.- Those asserting existence in a wide sense. These are typically of the form "N is P" for singular N, or "some S is P".
- Those asserting existence in a narrow sense. These are typically of the form "N exists" or "S's exist".
The problem is then evaded as follows. "Pegasus
flies" implies existence in the wide sense, for it implies that
something flies. But it does not imply existence in the narrow
sense, for we deny existence in this sense by saying that Pegasus
does not exist. In effect, the world of all things divides, on this
view, into those (like Socrates, the
planet Venus,
and New York City) that have existence in the narrow sense, and
those (like Sherlock
Holmes, the goddess Venus,
and Minas
Tirith) that do not.
However, common sense suggests the non-existence
of such things as fictional
characters or places.
European views
Influenced by the views of Brentano's pupil Alexius Meinong, and by Edmund Husserl, Germanophone and Francophone philosophy took a different direction regarding the question of existence. Existentialism has been a major strand of continental philosophy in the twentieth century.Endnotes
References
- Antoine Arnauld and Pierre Nicole 'Logic', or The Art of Thinking, (known as the Port-Royal Logic), translated J. Buroker, Cambridge 1996
- Mill, J.S., A System of Logic, 8th edition 1908
- Loux, M., Ockham's Theory Of Terms (translation of book I of the Summa Logicae c-1327).
Further reading
- Plato, The Republic, translated by Desmond Lee, Penguin Classics, 2003, ISBN 0140449140, ISBN-13: 978-0140449143
- Aristotle, The Metaphysics, translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred, Penguin Classics, 1999, ISBN 0140446192, ISBN-13: 978-0140446197
- Heraclitus, Fragments, James Hilton, forward, Brooks Hexton, translator, Penguin Classics, 2003, ISBN 0142437654, ISBN-13: 978-0142437650.
- The Meaning of Life, Terry Eagleton, Oxford University Press, 2007, ISBN 0199210705 ISBN-13: 978-0199210701
- The Story of Philosophy, Bryan Magee, Dorling Kindersley Lond. 1998, ISBN 0-7513-0590-1
See also
External links
nonexistent in Catalan: Existència
nonexistent in Czech: Existence
nonexistent in German: Existenz
nonexistent in Spanish: Existencia
nonexistent in Esperanto: Ekzisto
nonexistent in French: Existence
nonexistent in Galician: Existencia
nonexistent in Korean: 존재
nonexistent in Italian: Esistenza
nonexistent in Hebrew: קיום
nonexistent in Hungarian: A létező
nonexistent in Dutch: Bestaan
nonexistent in Japanese: 存在
nonexistent in Polish: Egzystencja
nonexistent in Portuguese: Existência
nonexistent in Russian: Существование
nonexistent in Simple English: Existence
nonexistent in Slovak: Existencia
nonexistent in Serbian: Постојање
nonexistent in Swedish: Existens
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
absconded, absent, away, deleted, departed, devoid, disappeared, existless, extinct, fancied, fictive, gone, gone away, illusory, imaginary, imaginational, imagined, lacking, lost, lost to sight, lost to view,
minus, missing, negative, no longer present, no
more, nonattendant,
not found, not present, notional, null, omitted, out of sight, past and
gone, subtracted,
supposititious,
taken away, unactual,
unexisting, unreal, vacuous, vanished, visional, void, wanting, without
being