Dictionary Definition
consciousness
Noun
1 an alert cognitive state in which you are aware
of yourself and your situation; "he lost consciousness" [ant:
unconsciousness]
2 having knowledge of; "he had no awareness of
his mistakes"; "his sudden consciousness of the problem he faced";
"their intelligence and general knowingness was impressive" [syn:
awareness, cognizance, cognisance, knowingness]
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Pronunciation
Translations
awareness
- Czech: vědomí
- Danish: bevidsthed
- Dutch: bewustzijn
- Estonian: teadvus
- Finnish: tajunta, taju
- French: conscience
- German: Bewusstsein
- Hebrew: מודעות (muda'ut)
- Hungarian: tudatosság, tudat
- Italian: conoscenza, coscienza
- Latvian: samaņa
- Romanian: conştiinţă
- Slovak: vedomie
- Swedish: medvetande
See also
Extensive Definition
portal Mind and
Brain Consciousness is a state that defies definition, but
which may involve thoughts, sensations, perceptions, moods,
emotions, dreams, and an awareness of
self,
although not necessarily all of these. Consciousness is a point of
view, an I, or what Thomas Nagel
called the existence of "something that it is like" to be
something. Julian
Jaynes has emphasized that "Consciousness is not the same as
cognition and should be sharply distinguished from it. ... The most
common error ... is to confuse consciousness with
perception."
Ned Block
divides consciousness into phenomenal consciousness, which is
subjective experience itself (being something), and access
consciousness, which refers to the availability of information to
processing systems in the brain (being conscious of
something).
The issue of what consciousness is, and to what
extent and in what sense it exists, is the subject of much research
in philosophy
of mind, psychology, neuroscience, cognitive
science, and artificial
intelligence. Issues of practical concern include how the
presence of consciousness can be assessed in severely ill
individuals; to what extent non-humans are self conscious; at what
point in fetal development consciousness begins; and whether
computers can achieve conscious states.
In common parlance, consciousness denotes being
awake and responsive to
the environment,
in contrast to being asleep or in a coma.
Etymology
"Consciousness" derives from Latin conscientia
which primarily means moral conscience. In the
literal sense, "conscientia" (or "con scientia") means
knowledge-with, that is, shared knowledge. The word first appears
in Latin juridic texts by writers such as Cicero. Here,
conscientia is the knowledge that a witness has of the deed of
someone else. In Christian theology, conscience stands for the
moral conscience in which our actions and intentions are registered
and which is only fully known to God. Medieval writers such as
Thomas
Aquinas describe the conscientia as the act by which we apply
practical and moral knowledge to our own actions. René
Descartes has been said to be the first philosopher to use
"conscientia" in a way that does not seem to fit this traditional
meaning, and, as a consequence, the translators of his writings in
other languages like French and English coined new words in order
to denote merely psychological consciousness. These are, for
instance, conscience,
and Bewusstsein.
However, it has also been argued that John Locke was
in fact the first one to use the modern meaning of consciousness in
his
Essay Concerning Human Understanding, although it remains
closely intertwined with moral conscience (I may be held morally
responsible only for the act of which I am conscious of having
achieved; and my personal identity - my self
- goes as far as my consciousness extends itself). The modern sense
of "consciousness" was therefore first found not in Descartes' work
- who sometimes used the word in a modern sense, but did not
distinguish it as much as Locke would do -, but in Locke's text.
The contemporary sense of the word (consciousness associated to the
idea of
personal identity, which is assured by the repeated
consciousness of oneself) was therefore introduced by Locke; but
the word "conscience" itself was coined by Pierre Costes, French
translator of Locke. Henceforth, the modern sense first appeared in
Locke's works, but the word itself first appeared in the French
language. Locke's influence upon the concept can be found in
Samuel
Johnson's celebrated Dictionary, in
which Johnson abstains from offering a definition of
"consciousness," choosing instead to simply quote Locke.
Philosophical approaches
There are many philosophical stances on consciousness, including: behaviorism, dualism, idealism, functionalism, reflexive monism, phenomenalism, phenomenology and intentionality, physicalism, emergentism, mysticism, personal identity etc.Phenomenal and access consciousness
Phenomenal consciousness (P-consciousness) is simply experience; it is moving, coloured forms, sounds, sensations, emotions and feelings with our bodies and responses at the center. These experiences, considered independently of any impact on behavior, are called qualia. The hard problem of consciousness was formulated by Chalmers in 1996, dealing with the issue of "how to explain a state of phenomenal consciousness in terms of its neurological basis" (Block 2004).Access consciousness (A-consciousness) is the
phenomenon whereby information in our minds is accessible for
verbal report, reasoning, and the control of behavior. So, when we
perceive, information
about what we perceive is often access conscious; when we introspect, information
about our thoughts is access conscious; when we remember, information about the
past (e.g., something that we learned) is often access
conscious; and so on. Chalmers thinks that access consciousness is
less mysterious than phenomenal consciousness, so that it is held
to pose one of the easy problems of consciousness. Dennett denies
that there is a "hard problem", asserting that the totality of
consciousness can be understood in terms of impact on behavior, as
studied through heterophenomenology.
There have been numerous approaches to the processes that act on
conscious experience from instant to instant. Philosophers who have
explored this problem include Gerald
Edelman, Edmund
Husserl and Daniel
Dennett. Daniel
Dennett (1988) suggests that what people think of as phenomenal
consciousness, such as qualia, are judgments and consequent
behaviour. He extends this analysis (Dennett, 1996) by arguing that
phenomenal consciousness can be explained in terms of access
consciousness, denying the existence of qualia, hence denying the
existence of a "hard problem." Chalmers, on the other hand, makes a
strong case for the hard problem, and shows that all of Dennett's
supposed explanatory processes merely address aspects of the easy
problem, albeit disgused in obfuscating verbiage. Eccles and others
have pointed out the difficulty of explaining the evolution of
qualia, or of 'minds' which experience them, given that all the
processes governing evolution are physical and so have no direct
access to them. There is no guarantee that all people have minds,
nor any way to verify whether one does or does not possess one. The
possibility has indeed been proposed that those denying the
existence of qualia, hence denying the existence of a "hard
problem," do so since they do not possess this faculty.
Events that occur in the mind or brain that are
not within phenomenal or access consciousness are known as subconscious
events.
The description and location of phenomenal consciousness
For centuries, philosophers have investigated phenomenal consciousness. René Descartes, who arrived at the famous dictum 'cogito ergo sum', wrote Meditations on First Philosophy in the seventeenth century. He described, extensively, what it is to be conscious. Conscious experience, according to Descartes, included such ideas as imaginings and perceptions laid out in space and time that are viewed from a point, and appearing as a result of some quality (qualia) such as color, smell, and so on. (Modern readers are often confused by this Descartes' notion of interchangeability between the terms 'idea' and 'imaginings.')Like Aristotle
Descartes defines ideas as extended things, as in this excerpt from
his Treatise on
Man:
- Now among these figures, it is not those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal surface of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those which are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H [where the seat of the imagination and the 'common sense' is located]. That is to say, it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the forms or images which the rational soul united to this machine will consider directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the senses.
Thus Descartes does not identify mental ideas or
'qualia' with activity
within the sense organs, or even with brain activity, but rather
with interaction between body and the 'rational soul', through the
mediating 'gland H'. This organ is
now known as the pineal
gland. Descartes notes that, anatomically, while the human brain
consists of two symmetrical hemispheres the pineal gland, which
lies close to the brain's centre, is singular. Thus he extrapolated
from this that it was the mediator between body and soul.
Other philosophers agreed with Descartes to
varying degrees. They include Nicolas
Malebranche, Thomas Reid,
John
Locke, David Hume and
Immanuel
Kant. Malebranche, for example, agreed with Descartes that the
human being was composed of two elements, body and mind, and that
conscious experience resided in the latter. He did, however,
disagree with Descartes as to the ease with which we might become
aware of our mental constitution, stating 'I am not my own light
unto myself'. David Hume and Immanuel Kant also differ from
Descartes, in that they avoid mentioning a place from which
experience is viewed (see "Further reading" below); certainly, few
if any modern philosophers have identified the pineal gland as the
seat of dualist interaction.
The extension of things in time was considered in
more detail by Kant and James. Kant wrote that "only on the
presupposition of time can we represent to ourselves a number of
things as existing at one and the same time [simultaneously] or at
different times [successively]." William
James stressed the extension of experience in time and said
that time is "the short duration of which we are immediately and
incessantly sensible."
When we look around a room or have a dream,
things are laid out in space and time and viewed as if from a
point. However, when philosophers and scientists consider the
location of the form and contents of this phenomenal consciousness,
there are fierce disagreements. As an example, Descartes proposed
that the contents are brain activity seen by a non-physical place
without extension (the Res Cogitans), which, in
Meditations on First Philosophy, he identified as the soul.
This idea is known as Cartesian
Dualism. Another example is found in the work of Thomas Reid
who thought the contents of consciousness are the world itself,
which becomes conscious experience in some way. This concept is a
type of Direct
realism. The precise physical substrate of conscious experience
in the world, such as photons, quantum fields, etc. is usually not
specified.
Other philosophers, such as George
Berkeley, have proposed that the contents of consciousness are
an aspect of minds and do not necessarily involve matter at all.
This is a type of Idealism. Yet
others, such as Leibniz, have
considered that each point in the universe is endowed with
conscious content. This is a form of Panpsychism.
Panpsychism is the belief that all matter, including rocks for
example, is sentient or conscious. The concept of the things in
conscious experience being impressions in the brain is a type of
representationalism,
and representationalism is a form of indirect
realism.
It is sometimes held that consciousness emerges
from the complexity of brain processing. The general label
'emergence' applies to
new phenomena that emerge from a physical basis without the
connection between the two explicitly specified.
Physicalists
claim that consciousness must arise from the neuronal interactions
in the brain, a hugely complicated machine with about 10 million
million neurones, each with thousands of excitatory and inhibitory
connections “votes,” with no mystery stuff. These neuronal
interactions must use voting mechanisms to deliver outcomes. But
voting systems can produce different results from the same voter
base and such voting result variations provide the required
indeterminacy
which provides freedom from rigid deterministic mechanisms (Welsby
PD. Problems with voting: the ultimate source? Int Journal of
Design & Nature Vol2, No 4, 2007). Sufficiently complex brains
will have a coordinating system which, when confronted by such
indeterminacy,
will become aware that it has been burdened with free will as it
has to determine which of the voting systems will be chosen to get
the result. This, according to the theory, is the origin of free
will; awareness of free will in turn leads to self-awareness, and
self-awareness is consciousness. Investigators have failed to agree
on an anatomical mechanism for consciousness. To those who support
the emergence theory, this is predictable because consciousness is
not an anatomical feature but a function; one that that emerges
from billions of neurones and their voting interactions, in the way
that a rainbow emerges from billions of raindrops.
Some theorists hold that phenomenal consciousness
poses an explanatory
gap. Colin McGinn
takes the New
Mysterianism position that it can't be solved, and Chalmers
criticizes
purely physical accounts of mental experiences based on the
idea that philosophical
zombies are logically possible and supports property
dualism. But others have proposed speculative scientific
theories to explain the explanatory gap, such as Quantum
mind,
space-time theories of consciousness, reflexive
monism, and
Electromagnetic theories of consciousness to explain the
correspondence between brain activity and experience.
Parapsychologists
sometimes appeal to the unproven concepts of psychokinesis or telepathy to support the
belief that consciousness is not confined to the brain.
Philosophical criticisms
From the eighteenth to twentieth centuries many
philosophers concentrated on relations, processes and thought as
the most important aspects of consciousness. These aspects would
later become known as "access consciousness" and this focus on
relations allowed philosophers such as Marx, Nietzsche and
Foucault
to claim that individual consciousness was dependent on such
factors as social relations, political relations and
ideology.
Locke's "forensic" notion of personal
identity founded on an individual conscious subject
would be criticized in the 19th century by Marx, Nietzsche, and
Freud
following different angles. Martin
Heidegger's concept of the Dasein ("Being-there") would
also be an attempt to think beyond the conscious subject.
Marx considered that social relations ontologically preceded
individual consciousness, and criticized the conception of a
conscious subject as an
ideological conception on which liberal political thought was
founded. Marx in particular criticized the 1789
Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen,
considering that the so-called individual natural
rights were ideological fictions camouflaging social
inequality in the attribution of those rights. Later, Louis
Althusser would criticize the "bourgeois ideology of the
subject" through the concept of interpellation ("Hey,
you!").
Nietzsche, for his part, once wrote that "they
give you free will only
to later blame yourself", thus reversing the classical liberal conception of free
will in a critical account of the genealogy of consciousness as the
effect of guilt and ressentiment, which he
described in
On the Genealogy of Morals. Hence, Nietzsche was the first one
to make the claim that the modern notion of consciousness was
indebted to the modern system of penalty, which judged a man
according to his "responsibility",
that is by the consciousness through which acts can be attributed
to an individual subject: "I did this! this is me!". Consciousness
is thus related by Nietzsche to the classic philosopheme of
recognition which,
according to him, defines knowledge.
According to Pierre
Klossowski (1969), Nietzsche considered consciousness to be a
hypostatization of
the body, composed of
multiple forces (the "Will
to Power"). According to him, the subject was only a
"grammatical fiction": we believed in the existence of an
individual subject, and therefore of a specific author of each act,
insofar as we speak. Therefore, the conscious subject is dependent
on the existence of language, a claim which would
be generalized by
critical discourse analysis (see for example Judith
Butler).
Michel
Foucault's analysis of the creation of the individual subject
through disciplines,
in Discipline
and Punish (1975), would extend Nietzsche's genealogy of
consciousness and personal identity - i.e. individualism - to the
change in the juridico-penal system: the emergence of penology and the
disciplinization of the individual subject through the creation of
a penal system which judged not the acts as it alleged to, but the
personal identity of the wrong-doer. In other words, Foucault
maintained that, by judging not the acts (the crime), but the
person behind those acts (the criminal), the modern penal system
was not only following the philosophical definition of
consciousness, once again demonstrating the imbrications between
ideas and social
institutions ("material ideology" as Althusser
would call it); it was by itself creating the individual person,
categorizing and dividing the masses into a category of poor but
honest and law-abiding citizens and another category of
"professional criminals" or recidivists.
Gilbert Ryle
has argued that traditional understandings of consciousness depend
on a Cartesian outlook that divides into mind and body, mind and
world. He proposed that we speak not of minds, bodies, and the
world, but of individuals, or persons, acting in the world. Thus,
by saying 'consciousness,' we end up misleading ourselves by
thinking that there is any sort of thing as consciousness separated
from behavioral and linguistic understandings.
The failure to produce a workable definition of
consciousness also raises formidable philosophical questions. It
has been argued that when Antonio
Damasio defines consciousness as "an organism's awareness of
its own self and its surroundings", the definition has not escaped
circularity, because awareness in that context can be considered a
synonym for consciousness.
The notion of consciousness as passive awareness
can be contrasted with the notion of the active construction of
mental
representations. Maturana and Varela showed that the brain is
massively involved with creating worlds of experience for us with
meager input from the senses. Evolutionary biologist Richard
Dawkins sums up the interactive view of experience: "In a way,
what sense organs do is assist our brains to construct a useful
model and it is this model that we move around in. It is a kind of
virtual reality simulation of the world."
Consciousness and language
Because humans express their conscious states using language, it is tempting to equate language abilities and consciousness. There are, however, speechless humans (infants, feral children, aphasics, severe forms of autism), to whom consciousness is attributed despite language lost or not yet acquired. Moreover, the study of brain states of non-linguistic primates, in particular the macaques, has been used extensively by scientists and philosophers in their quest for the neural correlates of the contents of consciousness.Julian
Jaynes argued to the contrary, in
The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral
Mind, that for consciousness (which he defines as not merely
perception of an object, but awareness that one is an entity which
is perceiving it) to arise in a person, language needs to have
reached a fairly high level of complexity. According to Jaynes,
human consciousness emerged as recently as 1300 BCE or thereabouts.
Some philosophers, including W.V. Quine,
and some neuroscientists,
including Christof
Koch, contest this hypothesis, arguing that it suggests that
prior to this "discovery" of consciousness, experience simply did
not exist. Ned Block
argued that Jaynes had confused consciousness with the concept of
consciousness, the latter being what was discovered between the
Iliad and the Odyssey. Daniel
Dennett points out that these approaches misconceive Jaynes's
definition of consciousness as more than mere perception or
awareness of an object. He notes that consciousness is like money
in that having the thing requires having the concept of it, so it
is a revolutionary proposal and not a ridiculous error to suppose
that consciousness only emerges when its concept does.
Other approaches
Cognitive neuroscience
Modern investigations into and discoveries about
consciousness are based on psychological
statistical
studies and case studies
of consciousness states and the deficits caused by lesions, stroke, injury, or surgery that disrupt the normal
functioning of human senses and cognition. These discoveries
suggest that the mind is a
complex structure derived from various localized functions that are
bound
together with a unitary awareness.
Several studies point to common mechanisms in
different clinical conditions that lead to loss of consciousness.
Persistent vegetative state (PVS) is a condition in which an
individual loses the higher cerebral powers of the brain, but
maintains sleep-wake cycles with full or partial autonomic
functions. Studies comparing PVS with healthy, awake subjects
consistently demonstrate an impaired connectivity between the
deeper (brainstem and thalamic) and the upper (cortical) areas of
the brain. In addition, it is agreed that the general brain
activity in the cortex is lower in the PVS state. Some electroneurobiological
interpretations of consciousness characterize this loss of
consciousness as a loss of the ability to resolve time (similar to
playing an old phonographic record at very slow or very rapid
speed), along a continuum that starts with inattention, continues
on sleep, and arrives to coma and death . It is likely that
different components of consciousness can be teased apart with
anesthetics,
sedatives and hypnotics. These drugs appear
to differentially act on several brain areas to disrupt, to varying
degrees, different components of consciousness. The ability to
recall information, for example, may be disrupted by anesthetics
acting on the hippocampal cortex. Neurons in this region are
particularly sensitive to anesthetics at the time loss of recall
occurs. Direct anesthetic actions on hippocampal neurons have been
shown to underlie EEG effects that occur in humans and animals
during loss of recall (MacIver
et al 1996; see also: http://www.stanford.edu/group/maciverlab/research.html).
Loss of consciousness also occurs in other
conditions, such as general (tonic-clonic) epileptic
seizures, in general
anaesthesia, maybe even in deep (slow-wave) sleep. At present, the
best-supported hypotheses about such cases of loss of consciousness
(or loss of time resolution) focus on the need for 1) a widespread
cortical network, including particularly the frontal, parietal and
temporal cortices, and 2) cooperation between the deep layers of
the brain, especially the thalamus, and the upper layers, the
cortex. Such hypotheses go under the common term "globalist
theories" of consciousness, due to the claim for a widespread,
global network necessary for consciousness to interact with
non-mental reality in the first place.
Brain chemistry affects human consciousness.
Sleeping drugs (such as Midazolam =
Dormicum) can bring the brain from the awake condition (conscious)
to the sleep (unconscious). Wake-up drugs such as Anexate reverse
this process. Many other drugs (such as alcohol, nicotine, Tetrahydrocannabinol
(THC), heroin, cocaine, LSD, MDMA) have a
consciousness-changing effect.
There is a neural link between the left and right
hemispheres of the brain, known as the corpus
callosum. This link is sometimes surgically severed to control
severe seizures in epilepsy patients. This procedure was first
performed by Roger Sperry
in the 1960s. Tests of these patients have shown that, after the
link is completely
severed, the hemispheres are no longer able to communicate,
leading to certain problems that usually arise only in test
conditions. For example, while the left side of the brain can
verbally describe what is going on in the right visual field, the
right hemisphere is essentially mute, instead relying on its
spatial abilities to interact with the world on the left visual
field. Some say that it is as if two separate minds now share the
same skull, but both still represent themselves as a single "I" to
the outside world.
The bilateral removal of the centromedian
nucleus (part of the Intra-laminar nucleus of the Thalamus)
appears to abolish consciousness, causing coma, PVS, severe mutism
and other features that mimic brain death.
The centromedian nucleus is also one of the principal sites of
action of general anaesthetics and anti-psychotic drugs. This
evidence suggests that a functioning thalamus is necessary, but not
sufficient, for human consciousness.
Neurophysiological studies in awake, behaving
monkeys point to advanced cortical areas in prefrontal cortex and
temporal lobes as carriers of neuronal correlates of consciousness.
Christof
Koch and Francis
Crick argued that
neuronal mechanisms of consciousness are intricately related to
prefrontal cortex — the most advanced cortical area.
Rodolfo
Llinas proposes that consciousness results from
recurrent thalamo-cortical resonance where the specific (dorsal
thalamus) thalamocortical system (content) and the non-specific
(centromedial thalamus) thalamocortical system (context) interact
at gamma band frequency via time coincidence. According to this
view the "I" represents a global predictive function required for
intentionality. Experimental work of Steven Wise, Mikhail
Lebedev and their colleagues supports this view. They
demonstrated that activity of prefrontal cortex neurons reflects
illusory perceptions of movements of visual stimuli. Nikos
Logothetis and colleagues made similar observations on visually
responsive neurons in the temporal lobe. These neurons reflect the
visual perception in the situation when conflicting visual images
are presented to different eyes (i.e., bistable percepts during
binocular rivalry). The studies of blindsight — vision
without awareness after lesions to parts of the visual system such
as the primary visual cortex — performed by Lawrence
Weiskrantz and David P. Carey provided important insights on how
conscious perception arises in the brain. In recent years the
theory of two visual streams, vision for perception versus vision
for action was developed by Melvyn Goodale, David Milner and
others. According to this theory, visual perception arises as the
result of processing of visual information by the ventral stream
areas (located mostly in the temporal lobe), whereas the dorsal
stream areas (located mostly in the parietal lobe) process visual
information unconsciously. For example, quick catching of the ball
would engage mostly the dorsal stream areas, and viewing a painting
would be handled by the ventral stream. Overall, these studies show
that conscious versus unconscious behaviors can be linked to
specific brain areas and patterns of neuronal activation.. However,
neuroscience only focuses on the
neural correlates of consciousness. The
hard problem of consciousness is to explain how all these flows
and electrochemical processes in the brain give rise to the inner
experience of subjective awareness.
One of the promising approaches in modern
Neuroscience is Operational
Architectonicstheory of brain-mind functioning developed by
Andrew and Alexander Fingelkurts. This theory states that
whenever any pattern of phenomenality (including reflective
thought) is instantiated, there is neuro-physiological pattern
(revealed directly by EEG) of appropriate kind that corresponds to
it. These neuron-physiological EEG patterns (expressed as the
virtual operational modules) are brought to existence by joint
operations of many functional and transient neuronal assemblies in
the brain. The activity of neuronal assemblies per se is 'hidden'
in the complex nonstationary structure of EEG field. Therefore, a
proper EEG analysis is needed that would be able to reveal the EEG
architecture which reflects or instantiates the kind of phenomenal
world (considering that there should be the ‘well-defined’ and
‘well-detected’ EEG phenomena) which humans subjectively
experience. Currently available EEG methods can reveal the EEG
architecture which is amazingly similar to the architecture of a
phenomenal world of consciousness (see review on EEG and Operational
Architectonics).
Evolutionary biology
Evolutionary biology, which by its own definition
is strictly concerned with the origin of species from a common
descent, does not know of any natural mechanism that could have
produced the trait of self
awareness. Given the non-physical nature of consciousness and
the fact that the earliest life forms in the evolutionary timeline
never possessed self awareness, consciousness appears to have
originated from a domain outside the known natural world.
Evolutionary biologists who try to explain the origins of
consciousness from an evolutionary perspective, do so under the
assumption that consciousness was a product of evolution.
Consciousness can be viewed from the evolutionary
biology approach as an adaptation because it is a
trait that increases the
fitness of its
possessor. Consciousness also adheres to John Alcock's
theory of animal behavioral adaptations because it possesses both
proximate and ultimate causes.
The proximate causes for consciousness, i.e. how
consciousness evolved in organisms, was elucidated by John C.
Eccles in his paper "Evolution of consciousness." In it, he stated
that special anatomical and physical properties of the mammalian
cerebral
cortex gave rise to consciousness. This is further evidenced by
the work of Gerhard Roth, who stated that "Among all features of
vertebrate brains, the size of cortex or structures homologous to
the mammalian cortex as well as the number of neurons and synapses
contained in these structures correlate most clearly with the
complexity of cognitive functions including states of
consciousness." Roth also states that the high-order consciousness
possessed by humans is most likely the result of a very large
number of cortical neurons, a prolonged period of
ontogenetic plasticity of cortical synapses, and the presence of
centers underlying syntactical language. One theory for the
evolution of consciousness and language is that it was an
evolutionary "arms race" driven by the counter one's rivals within
society.Regardless of the adaptive complexity theory, several
functions of consciousness were outlined by Bernard J. Baars.
Physical
Even at the dawn of Newtonian science, Leibniz and many others were suggesting physical theories of consciousness. Modern physical theories of consciousness can be divided into three types: theories to explain behaviour and access consciousness, theories to explain phenomenal consciousness and theories to explain the quantum mechanical (QM) Quantum mind. Theories that seek to explain behaviour are an everyday part of neuroscience, some of these theories of access consciousness, such as Edelman's theory, contentiously identify phenomenal consciousness with reflex events in the brain. Theories that seek to explain phenomenal consciousness directly, such as Space-time theories of consciousness and Electromagnetic theories of consciousness, have been available for almost a century, but have not yet been confirmed by experiment. Theories that attempt to explain the QM measurement problem include Pribram and Bohm's Holonomic brain theory, Hameroff and Penrose's Orch-OR theory and the Many-minds interpretation. Some of these QM theories offer descriptions of phenomenal consciousness, as well as QM interpretations of access consciousness. None of the quantum mechanical theories has been confirmed by experiment, and there are philosophers who argue that QM has no bearing on consciousness.There is also a concerted effort in the field of
Artificial
Intelligence to create digital computer programs that can
simulate
consciousness.
Functions
We generally agree that our fellow human beings are conscious, and that much simpler life forms, such as bacteria, are not. Many of us attribute consciousness to higher-order animals such as dolphins and primates; academic research is investigating the extent to which animals are conscious. This suggests the hypothesis that consciousness has co-evolved with life, which would require it to have some sort of added value, especially survival value. People have therefore looked for specific functions and benefits of consciousness. Bernard Baars (1997), for instance, states that "consciousness is a supremely functional adaptation" and suggests a variety of functions in which consciousness plays an important, if not essential, role: prioritization of alternatives, problem solving, decision making, brain processes recruiting, action control, error detection, planning, learning, adaptation, context creation, and access to information. Antonio Damasio (1999) regards consciousness as part of an organism's survival kit, allowing planned rather than instinctual responses. He also points out that awareness of self allows a concern for one's own survival, which increases the drive to survive, although how far consciousness is involved in behaviour is an actively debated issue. Many psychologists, such as radical behaviorists, and many philosophers, such as those that support Ryle's approach, would maintain that behavior can be explained by non-conscious processes akin to artificial intelligence, and might consider consciousness to be epiphenomenal or only weakly related to function.Regarding the primary function of conscious
processing, a recurring idea in recent theories is that phenomenal
states somehow integrate neural activities and
information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002). This has been called the integration
consensus. However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of
information are integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds
can be integrated without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of
information are capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g.,
neural activity related to vegetative functions, reflexes,
unconscious motor programs, low-level perceptual analyses, etc.)
and many kinds can be disseminated and combined with other kinds
without consciousness, as in intersensory interactions such as the
ventriloquism effect (cf., Morsella, 2005).
Ervin Laszlo
argues that self-awareness,
the ability to make observations of oneself, evolved. Emile
Durkheim formulated the concept of so called collective
consciousness, which is essential for organization of human,
social relations. The accelerating drive of human race to
explorations, cognition, understanding and technological
progresshttp://math.tulane.edu/~tipler/
can be explained by some features of collective
consciousness (collective self - concepts) and collective
intelligence
Tests
As there is no clear definition of consciousness and no empirical measure exists to test for its presence, it has been argued that due to the nature of the problem of consciousness, empirical tests are intrinsically impossible. However, several tests have been developed which attempt to provide an operational definition of consciousness and try to determine whether computers and other non-human animals can demonstrate through their behavior, by passing these tests, that they are conscious.In medicine, several neurological and brain
imaging techniques, like EEG and fMRI, have proven useful for
physical measures of brain activity associated with consciousness.
This is particularly true for
EEG measures during anesthesiahttp://www.stanford.edu/group/maciverlab/research.html
that can provide an indication of anesthetic depth, although with
still limited accuracies of ~ 70 % and a high degree of patient and
drug variability seen.
Turing
Though often thought of as a test for consciousness, the Turing test (named after computer scientist Alan Turing, who first proposed it) is actually a test to determine whether or not a computer satisfied his operational definition of "intelligent" (which is actually quite different from a test for consciousness or self-awareness). This test is commonly cited in discussion of artificial intelligence. The essence of the test is based on "the Imitation Game", in which a human experimenter attempts to converse, via computer keyboards, with two others. One of the others is a human (who, it is assumed, is conscious) while the other is a computer. Because all of the conversation is via keyboards (teletypes, in Turing's original conception) no cues such as voice, prosody, or appearance will be available to indicate which is the human and which is the computer. If the human is unable to determine which of the conversants is human, and which is a computer, the computer is said to have "passed" the Turing test (satisfied Turing's operational definition of "intelligent").The Turing test has generated a great deal of
research and philosophical debate. For example, Daniel
Dennett and Douglas
Hofstadter argue that anything capable of passing the Turing
test is necessarily conscious, while David
Chalmers, argues that a philosophical
zombie could pass the test, yet fail to be conscious.
It has been argued that the question itself is
excessively anthropomorphic. Edsger
Dijkstra commented that "The question of whether a computer can
think is no more interesting than the question of whether a
submarine can swim", expressing the view that different words are
appropriate for the workings of a machine to those of animals even
if they produce similar results, just as submarines are not
normally said to swim.
Philosopher John Searle
developed a thought
experiment, the Chinese room
argument, which is intended to show problems with the Turing Test.
Searle asks the reader to imagine a non-Chinese speaker in a room
in which there are stored a very large number of Chinese
symbols and rule books. Questions are passed to the person in the
form of written Chinese symbols via a slot, and the person responds
by looking up the symbols and the correct replies in the rule
books. Based on the purely input-output operations, the "Chinese
room" gives the appearance of understanding Chinese. However, the
person in the room understands no Chinese at all. This argument has
been the subject of intense philosophical debate since it was
introduced in 1980, even leading to edited volumes on this topic
alone.
The application of the Turing test to human
consciousness has even led to an annual competition, the Loebner
Prize with "Grand Prize of $100,000 and a Gold Medal for the
first computer whose responses were indistinguishable from a
human's." For a summary of research on the Turing Test, see
here.
With the mirror test,
devised by Gordon
Gallup in the 1970s, one is interested in whether animals are
able to recognize themselves in a mirror. The classic example of
the test involves placing a spot of coloring on the skin or fur
near the individual's forehead and seeing if they attempt to remove
it or at least touch the spot, thus indicating that they recognize
that the individual they are seeing in the mirror is themselves.
Humans (older than 18 months), great apes
(except for gorillas),
bottlenose
dolphins, pigeons
http://ww2.lafayette.edu/~allanr/mirror.html,
and elephants
http://www.newscientist.com/article/dn10402-elephants-see-themselves-in-the-mirror.html
have all been observed to pass this test. The test is usually
carried out with an identical 'spot' being placed elsewhere on the
head with a non-visible material as a control, to assure the
subject is not responding to the touch stimuli of the spot's
presence. Proponents of the
hard problem of consciousness claim that the mirror test only
demonstrates that some animals possess a particular cognitive
capacity for modelling their environment, but not for the presence
of phenomenal consciousness per se.
Delay
One problem researchers face is distinguishing nonconscious reflexes and instinctual responses from conscious responses. Neuroscientists Francis Crick and Christof Koch have proposed that by placing a delay between stimulus and execution of action, one may determine the extent of involvement of consciousness in an action of a biological organism.For example, when psychologists Larry Squire
and Robert Clark
combined a tone of a specific pitch with a puff of air to the eye,
test subjects came to blink their eyes in anticipation of the puff
of air when the appropriate tone was played. When the puff of air
followed a half of a second later, no such conditioning occurred.
When subjects were asked about the experiment, only those who were
asked to pay attention could consciously distinguish which tone
preceded the puff of air.
Ability to delay the response to an action
implies that the information must be stored in short-term memory,
which is conjectured to be a closely associated prerequisite for
consciousness. However, this test is only valid for biological
organisms. While it is simple to create a computer program that
passes, such success does not suggest anything beyond a clever
programmer.
See also
* Attention- Binocular rivalry
- Blindsight
- Change blindness
- Cognitive science
- Iconic memory
- Multistable perception
- Neural correlates of consciousness
- Neural Darwinism
- Psyche (psychology)
- Reticular activating system
- Short term memory
- Society of Mind
- Split brain
- Stream of consciousness (psychology)
- Unconscious mind
- Visual short term memory
- Consciousness (Buddhism)
- Higher Consciousness
- Mindstream
- 8-Circuit Model of Consciousness
- Bodymind
- Donald Davidson's swamp man thought experiment ("Knowing One Own's Mind", 1987)
- Dream argument
- False Consciousness (Marxism)
- Freedom of thought
- Homunculus
- Mental body
- Mind
- Mind at Large
- Mind-body problem
- Multiple Drafts theory (Daniel Dennett) cf. also Marvin Minsky
- New Mysterianism
- Personhood Theory
- Philosophy of mind
- Philosophy of perception
- Political consciousness, pertaining to marxist and post-marxist conceptions of consciousness.
- Qualia
- Stream of consciousness
- Supervenience
- Theory of mind
- Orch-OR theory
- Electromagnetic theories of consciousness
- Holonomic brain theory
- Quantum mind
- Space-time theories of consciousness
- Simulated Reality
- Association for Consciousness Exploration
- Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness
- Mind and Life Institute
- Mind Science Foundation
Notes
Further reading and external links
- Baars, B. (1997). In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. 2001 reprint: ISBN 978-0-19-514703-2
- Baars, Bernard J and Stan Franklin. 2003. How conscious experience and working memory interact. Trends in Cognitive Science 7: 166–172.
- Dynamics of Complex Systems, Chapter 3
- Damasio, A. (1999). The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt Press. ISBN 978-0-15-601075-7
- Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained, Boston: Little & Company. ISBN 978-0-316-18066-5
- Eccles, J.C. (1994), How the Self Controls its Brain, (Springer-Verlag).
- Franklin, S, B J Baars, U Ramamurthy, and Matthew Ventura. 2005. The role of consciousness in memory. Brains, Minds and Media 1: 1–38, pdf.
- Halliday, Eugene, Reflexive Self-Consciousness, ISBN 0-872240-01-1
- Harnad, S. (2005) What is Consciousness? New York Review of Books 52(11).
- James, W. (1902) The Varieties of Religious Experience
- Immanuel Kant (1781). Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman Kemp Smith with preface by Howard Caygill. Pub: Palgrave Macmillan.
- Koch, C. (2004). The Quest for Consciousness. Englewood, CO: Roberts & Company. ISBN 978-0-9747077-0-9
- John Locke (1689). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
- Libet, B., Freeman, A. & Sutherland, K. ed. (1999). The Volitional Brain: Towards a neuroscience of free will. Exeter, UK: Short Run Press, Ltd.
- Llinas R.,Ribary,U. Contreras,D. and Pedroarena, C. (1998) "The neuronal basis for consciousness" Phil. Tranns. R. Soc. London, B. 353:1841-1849
- Llinas R. (2001) "I of the Vortex. From Neurons to Self" MIT Press, Cambridge
- Metzinger, T. (2003). Being No One: the Self-model Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Metzinger, T. (Ed.) (2000). The Neural Correlates of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-13370-8
- Morgan, John H. (2007. In the Beginning: The Paleolithic Origins of Religious Consciousness. Cloverdale Books, South Bend. ISBN 978-1-929569-41-0
- Morsella, E. (2005). The Function of Phenomenal States: Supramodular Interaction Theory. Psychological Review, 112, 1000-1021.
- Penrose, R., Hameroff, S. R. (1996), 'Conscious Events as Orchestrated Space-Time Selections', Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3 (1), pp. 36-53.
- Pharoah, M.C. (online). Looking to systems theory for a reductive explanation of phenomenal experience and evolutionary foundations for higher order thought Retrieved Dec.14 2007.
- Sanz, R., López, I., Rodríguez, M. and Hernández, C. (2007) 'Principles for Consciousness in Integrated Cognitive Control'. Neural Networks, 20, pp. 938-946.
- Scaruffi, P. (2006). The Nature Of Consciousness. Omniware.
- Searle, J. (2004). Mind: A Brief Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Sternberg, E. (2007) Are You a Machine? The Brain, the Mind and What it Means to be Human. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.
- Velmans, M. (2000) Understanding Consciousness. London: Routledge/Psychology Press.
- Velmans, M. and Schneider, S. (Eds.)(2006) The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. New York: Blackwell.
- Anthropology of Consciousness
- Journal of Consciousness Studies
- Consciousness and Cognition
- Psyche
- Science & Consciousness Review
- ASSC e-print archive containing articles, book chapters, theses, conference presentations by members of the ASSC.
- Publications of the Tufts Center for Cognitive Studies, including Daniel Dennett
- David Chalmers' directory of online papers on consciousness
- Intuitions about Consciousness: Experimental Studies an article describing the folk intuitions about what is a conscious agent
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
- Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
- History of Consciousness Graduate Program, ("consciousness as forms of human expression and social action manifested in historical, cultural, and political contexts") at the University of California, Santa Cruz, headed by Dr. Angela Davis* Online lecture videos, from an undergraduate course taught by Christof Koch at Caltech on the neurobiological basis of consciousness in 2004.
- Piero Scaruffi's annotated bibliography on the mind
- Anesthesia and Drug effects on consciousness
- Brain Atlas, Brain Maps, Neuroinformatics
- Online course in consciousness at University of Virginia
- A survey course at University of Florida
- Edinburgh thesis (.ps) on consciousness including up-to-date reviews
- Consciousness-Related Engineering Anomaly Princeton
- Thy Mystery of Consciousness TIME.com
- Helen Keller Language and Consciousness
- Theory of the Red Blood Cells
- Swami Radhananda discusses subtlety and consciousness
- Jill Bolte Taylor - My Stroke of Insight
consciousness in Min Nan: Ì-sek
consciousness in Bulgarian: Съзнание
consciousness in Czech: Vědomí
consciousness in Danish: Bevidsthed
consciousness in German: Bewusstsein
consciousness in Estonian: Teadvus
consciousness in Spanish: Consciente
consciousness in Spanish: Consciencia
consciousness in Persian: آگاهی
consciousness in French: Conscience
consciousness in Icelandic: Meðvitund
consciousness in Italian: Coscienza
(psicologia)
consciousness in Hebrew: תודעה
consciousness in Kurdish: Hişar
consciousness in Latvian: Apziņa
consciousness in Hungarian: Tudat
consciousness in Dutch: Bewustzijn
consciousness in Japanese: 意識
consciousness in Norwegian: Bevissthet
consciousness in Polish: Świadomość
consciousness in Portuguese: Consciência
consciousness in Russian: Сознание
consciousness in Albanian: Vetëdija
consciousness in Simple English:
Consciousness
consciousness in Finnish: Tietoisuus
consciousness in Swedish: Medvetande
consciousness in Turkish: Bilinç
consciousness in Yiddish: באוואוסטזיין
consciousness in Chinese: 意識
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
advertence, advertency, alertness, all-night vigil,
apperception,
appreciation,
appreciativeness,
assiduity, assiduousness, attention, attention span,
attentiveness,
awareness, brain, care, carefulness, cognition, cognizance, concentration, concern, consideration, diligence, ear, earnestness, experience, faculties, feeling, head, heed, heedfulness, insight, insomnia, insomniac, insomnolence, insomnolency, intellect, intellectual gifts,
intellectuals,
intelligence,
intentiveness,
intentness, lidless
vigil, mentality,
mindfulness,
noesis, note, notice, observance, observation, parts, percept, perception, realization, recognition, regard, regardfulness, remark, respect, response, response to stimuli,
restlessness,
sensation, sense, sense impression, sense
perception, senses,
sensibility, sensory
experience, sentience,
sleeplessness,
thought, tossing and
turning, vigil, wake, wakefulness, wise man,
wits